Well-ordering principle explained
Well-ordering principle should not be confused with Well-ordering theorem.
In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty subset of nonnegative integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of nonnegative integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which
precedes
if and only if
is either
or the sum of
and some nonnegative integer (other orderings include the ordering
; and
).
\{\ldots,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,\ldots\}
contains a
well-ordered subset, called the
natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.
Properties
Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second-order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:
- In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic.
- Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set
of natural numbers has an infimum, say
. We can now find an integer
such that
lies in the half-open interval
, and can then show that we must have
, and
in
.
- In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers
such that "
is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.
In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set
, assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the
contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "
minimal criminal" method and is similar in its nature to
Fermat's method of "
infinite descent".
Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).
Example applications
The well-ordering principle can be used in the following proofs.
Prime factorization
Theorem: Every integer greater than one can be factored as a product of primes. This theorem constitutes part of the Prime Factorization Theorem.
Proof (by well-ordering principle). Let
be the set of all integers greater than one that
cannot be factored as a product of primes. We show that
is empty.
Assume for the sake of contradiction that
is not empty. Then, by the well-ordering principle, there is a least element
;
cannot be prime since a prime number itself is considered a length-one product of primes. By the definition of non-prime numbers,
has factors
, where
are integers greater than one and less than
. Since
, they are not in
as
is the smallest element of
. So,
can be factored as products of primes, where
and
, meaning that
, a product of primes. This contradicts the assumption that
, so the assumption that
is nonempty must be false.
[2] Integer summation
Theorem:
for all positive integers
.
Proof. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that the above theorem is false. Then, there exists a non-empty set of positive integers
C=\{n\inN\mid1+2+3+...+n ≠
\}
. By the well-ordering principle,
has a minimum element
such that when
, the equation is false, but true for all positive integers less than
. The equation is true for
, so
;
is a positive integer less than
, so the equation holds for
as it is not in
. Therefore,
which shows that the equation holds for
, a contradiction. So, the equation must hold for all positive integers.
[2] Notes and References
- Book: Apostol, Tom . Introduction to Analytic Number Theory . Tom M. Apostol . 1976 . Springer-Verlag . New York . 0-387-90163-9 . 13 . registration .
- Book: Lehman . Eric . Meyer . Albert R . Leighton . F Tom . Mathematics for Computer Science . 2 May 2023.