Well-ordering principle explained

Well-ordering principle should not be confused with Well-ordering theorem.

In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty subset of nonnegative integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of nonnegative integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which

x

precedes

y

if and only if

y

is either

x

or the sum of

x

and some nonnegative integer (other orderings include the ordering

2,4,6,...

; and

1,3,5,...

).

\{\ldots,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,\ldots\}

contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.

Properties

Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second-order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:

A

of natural numbers has an infimum, say

a*

. We can now find an integer

n*

such that

a*

lies in the half-open interval

(n*-1,n*]

, and can then show that we must have

a*=n*

, and

n*

in

A

.

n

such that "

\{0,\ldots,n\}

is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.

In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set

S

, assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".

Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).

Example applications

The well-ordering principle can be used in the following proofs.

Prime factorization

Theorem: Every integer greater than one can be factored as a product of primes. This theorem constitutes part of the Prime Factorization Theorem.

Proof (by well-ordering principle). Let

C

be the set of all integers greater than one that cannot be factored as a product of primes. We show that

C

is empty.

Assume for the sake of contradiction that

C

is not empty. Then, by the well-ordering principle, there is a least element

n\inC

;

n

cannot be prime since a prime number itself is considered a length-one product of primes. By the definition of non-prime numbers,

n

has factors

a,b

, where

a,b

are integers greater than one and less than

n

. Since

a,b<n

, they are not in

C

as

n

is the smallest element of

C

. So,

a,b

can be factored as products of primes, where

a=p1p2...pk

and

b=q1q2...ql

, meaning that

n=p1p2...pkq1q2...ql

, a product of primes. This contradicts the assumption that

n\inC

, so the assumption that

C

is nonempty must be false.[2]

Integer summation

Theorem:

1+2+3+...+n=

n(n+1)
2
for all positive integers

n

.

Proof. Suppose for the sake of contradiction that the above theorem is false. Then, there exists a non-empty set of positive integers

C=\{n\inN\mid1+2+3+...+n

n(n+1)
2

\}

. By the well-ordering principle,

C

has a minimum element

c

such that when

n=c

, the equation is false, but true for all positive integers less than

c

. The equation is true for

n=1

, so

c>1

;

c-1

is a positive integer less than

c

, so the equation holds for

c-1

as it is not in

C

. Therefore, \begin1 + 2 + 3 + ... + (c - 1) &= \frac \\1 + 2 + 3 + ... + (c - 1) + c &= \frac + c\\&= \frac + \frac\\&= \frac\\&= \frac\endwhich shows that the equation holds for

c

, a contradiction. So, the equation must hold for all positive integers.[2]

Notes and References

  1. Book: Apostol, Tom . Introduction to Analytic Number Theory . Tom M. Apostol . 1976 . Springer-Verlag . New York . 0-387-90163-9 . 13 . registration .
  2. Book: Lehman . Eric . Meyer . Albert R . Leighton . F Tom . Mathematics for Computer Science . 2 May 2023.