Utilitarian rule explained
In social choice and operations research, the utilitarian rule (also called the max-sum rule) is a rule saying that, among all possible alternatives, society should pick the alternative which maximizes the sum of the utilities of all individuals in society.[1] It is a formal mathematical representation of the utilitarian philosophy, and is often justified by reference to Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem or the Von Neumann–Morgenstern theorem.
In the context of voting systems, the rule is called score voting.
Definition
Let
be a set of possible "states of the world" or "alternatives". Society wishes to choose a single state from
. For example, in a
single-winner election,
may represent the set of candidates; in a
resource allocation setting,
may represent all possible allocations of the resource.
Let
be a finite set, representing a collection of individuals. For each
, let
be a
utility function, describing the amount of happiness an individual
i derives from each possible state.
A social choice rule is a mechanism which uses the data
to select some element(s) from
which are "best" for society (the question of what "best" means is the basic problem of
social choice theory).
The utilitarian rule selects an element
which maximizes the
utilitarian sum
Tangible utility functions
The utilitarian rule is easy to interpret and implement when the functions ui represent some tangible, measurable form of utility. For example:
- Consider a problem of allocating wood among builders. The utility functions may represent their productive power –
is the number of buildings that agent
can build using
units of wood. The utilitarian rule then allocates the wood in a way that maximizes the number of buildings.
- Consider a problem of allocating a rare medication among patient. The utility functions may represent their chance of recovery –
is the probability of agent
to recover by getting
doses of the medication. The utilitarian rule then allocates the medication in a way that maximizes the
expected number of survivors.
Abstract utility functions
When the functions ui represent some abstract form of "happiness", the utilitarian rule becomes harder to interpret. For the above formula to make sense, it must be assumed that the utility functions
are both
cardinal and interpersonally comparable at a cardinal level.
The notion that individuals have cardinal utility functions is not that problematic. Cardinal utility has been implicitly assumed in decision theory ever since Daniel Bernoulli's analysis of the St. Petersburg paradox. Rigorous mathematical theories of cardinal utility (with application to risky decision making) were developed by Frank P. Ramsey, Bruno de Finetti, von Neumann and Morgenstern, and Leonard Savage. However, in these theories, a person's utility function is only well-defined up to an "affine rescaling". Thus, if the utility function
is valid description of her preferences, and if
are two constants with
, then the "rescaled" utility function
is an equally valid description of her preferences. If we define a new package of utility functions
using possibly different
and
for all
, and we then consider the utilitarian sum
then in general, the maximizer of
will
not be the same as the maximizer of
. Thus, in a sense, classic utilitarian social choice is not well-defined within the standard model of cardinal utility used in decision theory, unless a mechanism is specified to "calibrate" the utility functions of the different individuals.
Relative utilitarianism
Relative utilitarianism proposes a natural calibration mechanism. For every
, suppose that the values
mi := minxui(x) and Mi := maxxui(x)
are well-defined. (For example, this will always be true if
is finite, or if
is a compact space and
is a continuous function.) Then define
for all
. Thus,
is a "rescaled" utility function which has a minimum value of 0 and a maximum value of 1. The Relative Utilitarian social choice rule selects the element in
which maximizes the utilitarian sum
As an abstract social choice function, relative utilitarianism has been analyzed by Cao (1982),[2] Dhillon (1998), Karni (1998), Dhillon and Mertens (1999), Segal (2000), Sobel (2001) and Pivato (2008). (Cao (1982) refers to it as the "modified Thomson solution".)
The utilitarian rule and Pareto-efficiency
Every Pareto efficient social choice function is necessarily a utilitarian choice function, a result known as Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem. Specifically, any Pareto efficient social choice function must be a linear combination of the utility functions of each individual utility function (with strictly positive weights).
The utilitarian rule in specific contexts
In the context of voting, the utilitarian rule leads to several voting methods:
- Range voting (also called score voting or utilitarian voting) implements the relative-utilitarian rule by letting voters explicitly express their utilities to each alternative on a common normalized scale.
- Implicit utilitarian voting tries to approximate the utilitarian rule while letting the voters express only ordinal rankings over candidates.
In the context of resource allocation, the utilitarian rule leads to:
See also
Notes and References
- Book: Moulin, Hervé . Fair division and collective welfare . 2003 . MIT Press . 978-0-262-13423-1 . Cambridge, Mass..
- Book: Cao, Xiren. 1982 21st IEEE Conference on Decision and Control . Preference functions and bargaining solutions . 1982-12-01. http://dx.doi.org/10.1109/cdc.1982.268420. 164–171. IEEE. 10.1109/cdc.1982.268420. 30395654.
- Aziz . Haris . Huang . Xin . Mattei . Nicholas . Segal-Halevi . Erel . 2022-10-13 . Computing welfare-Maximizing fair allocations of indivisible goods . European Journal of Operational Research . 307 . 2 . 773–784 . en . 10.1016/j.ejor.2022.10.013 . 2012.03979 . 235266307 . 0377-2217.