In mathematics, particularly category theory, a representable functor is a certain functor from an arbitrary category into the category of sets. Such functors give representations of an abstract category in terms of known structures (i.e. sets and functions) allowing one to utilize, as much as possible, knowledge about the category of sets in other settings.
From another point of view, representable functors for a category C are the functors given with C. Their theory is a vast generalisation of upper sets in posets, and Yoneda's representability theorem generalizes Cayley's theorem in group theory.
Let C be a locally small category and let Set be the category of sets. For each object A of C let Hom(A, -) be the hom functor that maps object X to the set Hom(A,X).
A functor F : C → Set is said to be representable if it is naturally isomorphic to Hom(A, -) for some object A of C. A representation of F is a pair (A, Φ) where
Φ : Hom(A, -) → Fis a natural isomorphism.
A contravariant functor G from C to Set is the same thing as a functor G : Cop → Set and is commonly called a presheaf. A presheaf is representable when it is naturally isomorphic to the contravariant hom-functor Hom( -,A) for some object A of C.
According to Yoneda's lemma, natural transformations from Hom(A, -) to F are in one-to-one correspondence with the elements of F(A). Given a natural transformation Φ : Hom(A, -) → F the corresponding element u ∈ F(A) is given by
u=\PhiA(idA).
\PhiX(f)=(Ff)(u)
A universal element of a functor F : C → Set is a pair (A,u) consisting of an object A of C and an element u ∈ F(A) such that for every pair (X,v) consisting of an object X of C and an element v ∈ F(X) there exists a unique morphism f : A → X such that (Ff)(u) = v.A universal element may be viewed as a universal morphism from the one-point set to the functor F or as an initial object in the category of elements of F.
The natural transformation induced by an element u ∈ F(A) is an isomorphism if and only if (A,u) is a universal element of F. We therefore conclude that representations of F are in one-to-one correspondence with universal elements of F. For this reason, it is common to refer to universal elements (A,u) as representations.
X\toA
Consider a linear functional on a complex Hilbert space H, i.e. a linear function
F:H\toC
a\inH
\langlea,-\rangle
F(v)=\langlea,v\rangle
v\inH
H=L2(R)
styleF(v)=\langlea,v\rangle=\intRa(x)v(x)dx
a(x)\inH
infty | |
C=C | |
c(R) |
F(v)=v(0)
v(x)\inC
x=0
Thus, a function
a(x)
Representations of functors are unique up to a unique isomorphism. That is, if (A1,Φ1) and (A2,Φ2) represent the same functor, then there exists a unique isomorphism φ : A1 → A2 such that
-1 | |
\Phi | |
1 |
\circ\Phi2=Hom(\varphi,-)
Stated in terms of universal elements: if (A1,u1) and (A2,u2) represent the same functor, then there exists a unique isomorphism φ : A1 → A2 such that
(F\varphi)u1=u2.
Representable functors are naturally isomorphic to Hom functors and therefore share their properties. In particular, (covariant) representable functors preserve all limits. It follows that any functor which fails to preserve some limit is not representable.
Contravariant representable functors take colimits to limits.
Any functor K : C → Set with a left adjoint F : Set → C is represented by (FX, ηX(•)) where X = is a singleton set and η is the unit of the adjunction.
Conversely, if K is represented by a pair (A, u) and all small copowers of A exist in C then K has a left adjoint F which sends each set I to the Ith copower of A.
Therefore, if C is a category with all small copowers, a functor K : C → Set is representable if and only if it has a left adjoint.
The categorical notions of universal morphisms and adjoint functors can both be expressed using representable functors.
Let G : D → C be a functor and let X be an object of C. Then (A,φ) is a universal morphism from X to G if and only if (A,φ) is a representation of the functor HomC(X,G -) from D to Set. It follows that G has a left-adjoint F if and only if HomC(X,G -) is representable for all X in C. The natural isomorphism ΦX : HomD(FX, -) → HomC(X,G -) yields the adjointness; that is
\PhiX,Y\colonHomlD(FX,Y)\toHomlC(X,GY)
The dual statements are also true. Let F : C → D be a functor and let Y be an object of D. Then (A,φ) is a universal morphism from F to Y if and only if (A,φ) is a representation of the functor HomD(F -,Y) from C to Set. It follows that F has a right-adjoint G if and only if HomD(F -,Y) is representable for all Y in D.[2]