Thing-in-itself explained

In Kantian philosophy, the thing-in-itself (German: Ding an sich) is the status of objects as they are, independent of representation and observation. The concept of the thing-in-itself was introduced by the German philosopher Immanuel Kant, and over the following centuries was met with controversy among later philosophers.[1] It is closely related to Kant's concept of noumena or the objects of inquiry, as opposed to phenomena, its manifestations.

Kantian philosophy

In his doctrine of transcendental idealism, Kant argued the sum of all objects, the empirical world, is a complex of appearances whose existence and connection occur only in our representations.[2] Kant introduces the thing-in-itself as follows:

Criticism

F. H. Jacobi

The first to criticize the concept of a thing-in-itself was F. H. Jacobi, with the expression:

G. E. Schulze

The anonymously published work Aenesidemus was one of the most successful attacks against the project of Kant. According to Kant's teaching, things-in-themselves cannot cause appearances, since the category of causality can only find application on objects of experience. Kant, therefore, does not have the right to claim the existence of things-in-themselves.

This contradiction was subsequently generally accepted as being the main problem of the thing-in-itself. The attack on the thing-in-itself, and the skeptical work in general, had a big impact on Fichte, and Schopenhauer called G. E. Schulze, who was revealed to be the author, “the acutest" of Kant's opponents.[3]

Johann Gottlieb Fichte

Initially Fichte embraced Kantian philosophy, including a thing-in-itself, but the work of Schulze made him revise his position.

The system which Fichte subsequently published, Science of Knowledge, scraps the thing-in-itself.[4]

Schopenhauer

In his "Critique of the Kantian Philosophy" appended to The World as Will and Representation (1818), Arthur Schopenhauer agreed with the critics that the manner in which Kant had introduced the thing-in-itself was inadmissible, but he considered that Kant was right to assert its existence and praised the distinction between thing-in-itself and appearance as Kant's greatest merit. As he wrote in volume 1 of his Parerga and Paralipomena, "Fragments of the History of Philosophy," §13:

Mainländer

A unique position is taken by Philipp Mainländer, who hailed Kant for breaking the rules of his own philosophy to proclaim the existence of a thing-in-itself.

See also

Notes and References

  1. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/maimon/. Salomon Maimon (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Salomon Maimon. 2021. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Perhaps the most obvious problem — and certainly one of the earliest — that Kant faces concerns the issue of the thing in itself..
  2. Book: Kant, Immanuel. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. § 52c. Paul Carus.
  3. Book: Schopenhauer, Arthur. The World as Will and Representation. 1 Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy. Kant’s greatest merit is the distinction of the phenomenon from the thing in itself … This defect, as is known, is the introduction of the thing in itself in the way chosen by him, the inadmissibleness of which was exposed at length by G. E. Schulze in "Aenesidemus " and was soon recognised as the untenable point of his system. … It is most remarkable that one of Kant’s opponents, and indeed the acutest of them, G. E. Schulze ….
  4. Book: C. Beiser, Frederick. German idealism : the struggle against subjectivism, 1781–1801. 2002. limited. 0-674-00769-7. 217. Harvard University Press . First, it eliminates the thing-in-itself and the given manifold..