T-norm fuzzy logics explained
T-norm fuzzy logics are a family of non-classical logics, informally delimited by having a semantics that takes the real unit interval [0, 1] for the system of truth values and functions called t-norms for permissible interpretations of conjunction. They are mainly used in applied fuzzy logic and fuzzy set theory as a theoretical basis for approximate reasoning.
T-norm fuzzy logics belong in broader classes of fuzzy logics and many-valued logics. In order to generate a well-behaved implication, the t-norms are usually required to be left-continuous; logics of left-continuous t-norms further belong in the class of substructural logics, among which they are marked with the validity of the law of prelinearity, (A → B) ∨ (B → A). Both propositional and first-order (or higher-order) t-norm fuzzy logics, as well as their expansions by modal and other operators, are studied. Logics that restrict the t-norm semantics to a subset of the real unit interval (for example, finitely valued Łukasiewicz logics) are usually included in the class as well.
Important examples of t-norm fuzzy logics are monoidal t-norm logic (MTL) of all left-continuous t-norms, basic logic (BL) of all continuous t-norms, product fuzzy logic of the product t-norm, or the nilpotent minimum logic of the nilpotent minimum t-norm. Some independently motivated logics belong among t-norm fuzzy logics, too, for example Łukasiewicz logic (which is the logic of the Łukasiewicz t-norm) or Gödel–Dummett logic (which is the logic of the minimum t-norm).
Motivation
As members of the family of fuzzy logics, t-norm fuzzy logics primarily aim at generalizing classical two-valued logic by admitting intermediary truth values between 1 (truth) and 0 (falsity) representing degrees of truth of propositions. The degrees are assumed to be real numbers from the unit interval [0, 1]. In propositional t-norm fuzzy logics, propositional connectives are stipulated to be truth-functional, that is, the truth value of a complex proposition formed by a propositional connective from some constituent propositions is a function (called the truth function of the connective) of the truth values of the constituent propositions. The truth functions operate on the set of truth degrees (in the standard semantics, on the [0, 1] interval); thus the truth function of an n-ary propositional connective c is a function Fc: [0, 1]n → [0, 1]. Truth functions generalize truth tables of propositional connectives known from classical logic to operate on the larger system of truth values.
T-norm fuzzy logics impose certain natural constraints on the truth function of conjunction. The truth function
of conjunction is assumed to satisfy the following conditions:
for all
x and
y in [0, 1]. This expresses the assumption that the order of fuzzy propositions is immaterial in conjunction, even if intermediary truth degrees are admitted.
for all
x,
y, and
z in [0, 1]. This expresses the assumption that the order of performing conjunction is immaterial, even if intermediary truth degrees are admitted.
then
for all
x,
y, and
z in [0, 1]. This expresses the assumption that increasing the truth degree of a conjunct should not decrease the truth degree of the conjunction.
- Neutrality of 1, that is,
for all
x in [0, 1]. This assumption corresponds to regarding the truth degree 1 as full truth, conjunction with which does not decrease the truth value of the other conjunct. Together with the previous conditions this condition ensures that also
for all
x in [0, 1], which corresponds to regarding the truth degree 0 as full falsity, conjunction with which is always fully false.
- Continuity of the function
(the previous conditions reduce this requirement to the continuity in either argument). Informally this expresses the assumption that microscopic changes of the truth degrees of conjuncts should not result in a macroscopic change of the truth degree of their conjunction. This condition, among other things, ensures a good behavior of (residual) implication derived from conjunction; to ensure the good behavior, however,
left-continuity (in either argument) of the function
is sufficient.
[1] In general t-norm fuzzy logics, therefore, only left-continuity of
is required, which expresses the assumption that a microscopic
decrease of the truth degree of a conjunct should not macroscopically decrease the truth degree of conjunction.
These assumptions make the truth function of conjunction a left-continuous t-norm, which explains the name of the family of fuzzy logics (t-norm based). Particular logics of the family can make further assumptions about the behavior of conjunction (for example, Gödel–Dummett logic requires its idempotence) or other connectives (for example, the logic IMTL (involutive monoidal t-norm logic) requires the involutiveness of negation).
All left-continuous t-norms
have a unique residuum, that is, a binary function
such that for all
x,
y, and
z in [0, 1],
if and only if
The residuum of a left-continuous t-norm can explicitly be defined as
(x ⇒ y)=\sup\{z\midz*x\ley\}.
This ensures that the residuum is the pointwise largest function such that for all
x and
y,
The latter can be interpreted as a fuzzy version of the
modus ponens rule of inference. The residuum of a left-continuous t-norm thus can be characterized as the weakest function that makes the fuzzy modus ponens valid, which makes it a suitable truth function for implication in fuzzy logic. Left-continuity of the t-norm is the necessary and sufficient condition for this relationship between a t-norm conjunction and its residual implication to hold.
Truth functions of further propositional connectives can be defined by means of the t-norm and its residuum, for instance the residual negation
or bi-residual equivalence
x\Leftrightarrowy=(x ⇒ y)*(y ⇒ x).
Truth functions of propositional connectives may also be introduced by additional definitions: the most usual ones are the minimum (which plays a role of another conjunctive connective), the maximum (which plays a role of a disjunctive connective), or the Baaz Delta operator, defined in [0, 1] as
if
and
otherwise. In this way, a left-continuous t-norm, its residuum, and the truth functions of additional propositional connectives determine the truth values of complex propositional formulae in [0, 1].
Formulae that always evaluate to 1 are called tautologies with respect to the given left-continuous t-norm
or
tautologies. The set of all
tautologies is called the
logic of the t-norm
as these formulae represent the laws of fuzzy logic (determined by the t-norm) that hold (to degree 1) regardless of the truth degrees of
atomic formulae. Some formulae are
tautologies with respect to a larger class of left-continuous t-norms; the set of such formulae is called the logic of the class. Important t-norm logics are the logics of particular t-norms or classes of t-norms, for example:
It turns out that many logics of particular t-norms and classes of t-norms are axiomatizable. The completeness theorem of the axiomatic system with respect to the corresponding t-norm semantics on [0, 1] is then called the standard completeness of the logic. Besides the standard real-valued semantics on [0, 1], the logics are sound and complete with respect to general algebraic semantics, formed by suitable classes of prelinear commutative bounded integral residuated lattices.
History
Some particular t-norm fuzzy logics have been introduced and investigated long before the family was recognized (even before the notions of fuzzy logic or t-norm emerged):
A systematic study of particular t-norm fuzzy logics and their classes began with Hájek's (1998) monograph Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic, which presented the notion of the logic of a continuous t-norm, the logics of the three basic continuous t-norms (Łukasiewicz, Gödel, and product), and the 'basic' fuzzy logic BL of all continuous t-norms (all of them both propositional and first-order). The book also started the investigation of fuzzy logics as non-classical logics with Hilbert-style calculi, algebraic semantics, and metamathematical properties known from other logics (completeness theorems, deduction theorems, complexity, etc.).
Since then, a plethora of t-norm fuzzy logics have been introduced and their metamathematical properties have been investigated. Some of the most important t-norm fuzzy logics were introduced in 2001, by Esteva and Godo (MTL, IMTL, SMTL, NM, WNM), Esteva, Godo, and Montagna (propositional ŁΠ),[6] and Cintula (first-order ŁΠ).[7]
Logical language
The logical vocabulary of propositional t-norm fuzzy logics standardly comprises the following connectives:
(
binary). In the context of other than t-norm-based fuzzy logics, the t-norm-based implication is sometimes called
residual implication or
R-implication, as its standard semantics is the residuum of the
t-norm that realizes strong conjunction.
(binary). In the context of substructural logics, the sign
and the names
group,
intensional,
multiplicative, or
parallel conjunction are often used for strong conjunction.
(binary), also called
lattice conjunction (as it is always realized by the
lattice operation of meet in algebraic semantics). In the context of substructural logics, the names
additive,
extensional, or
comparative conjunction are sometimes used for lattice conjunction. In the logic
BL and its extensions (though not in t-norm logics in general), weak conjunction is definable in terms of implication and strong conjunction, by
The presence of two conjunction connectives is a common feature of contraction-free
substructural logics.
(nullary);
or
are common alternative signs and
zero a common alternative name for the propositional constant (as the constants bottom and zero of substructural logics coincide in t-norm fuzzy logics). The proposition
represents the
falsity or
absurdum and corresponds to the classical truth value
false.
(
unary), sometimes called
residual negation if other negation connectives are considered, as it is defined from the residual implication by the reductio ad absurdum:
(binary), defined as
In t-norm logics, the definition is equivalent to
(binary), also called
lattice disjunction (as it is always realized by the
lattice operation of
join in algebraic semantics). In t-norm logics it is definable in terms of other connectives as
(nullary), also called
one and denoted by
or
(as the constants top and zero of substructural logics coincide in t-norm fuzzy logics). The proposition
corresponds to the classical truth value
true and can in t-norm logics be defined as
Some propositional t-norm logics add further propositional connectives to the above language, most often the following ones:
is a unary connective that asserts classical truth of a proposition, as the formulae of the form
behave as in classical logic. Also called the
Baaz Delta, as it was first used by Matthias Baaz for
Gödel–Dummett logic.
[8] The expansion of a t-norm logic
by the Delta connective is usually denoted by
- Truth constants are nullary connectives representing particular truth values between 0 and 1 in the standard real-valued semantics. For the real number
, the corresponding truth constant is usually denoted by
Most often, the truth constants for all rational numbers are added. The system of all truth constants in the language is supposed to satisfy the
bookkeeping axioms:
[9] etc. for all propositional connectives and all truth constants definable in the language.
(unary) can be added as an additional negation to t-norm logics whose residual negation is not itself
involutive, that is, if it does not obey the law of double negation
\neg\negA\leftrightarrowA
. A t-norm logic
expanded with involutive negation is usually denoted by
and called
with involution.
(binary). In the context of substructural logics it is also called
group,
intensional,
multiplicative, or
parallel disjunction. Even though standard in contraction-free substructural logics, in t-norm fuzzy logics it is usually used only in the presence of involutive negation, which makes it definable (and so axiomatizable) by de Morgan's law from strong conjunction:
- Additional t-norm conjunctions and residual implications. Some expressively strong t-norm logics, for instance the logic ŁΠ, have more than one strong conjunction or residual implication in their language. In the standard real-valued semantics, all such strong conjunctions are realized by different t-norms and the residual implications by their residua.
Well-formed formulae of propositional t-norm logics are defined from propositional variables (usually countably many) by the above logical connectives, as usual in propositional logics. In order to save parentheses, it is common to use the following order of precedence:
- Unary connectives (bind most closely)
- Binary connectives other than implication and equivalence
- Implication and equivalence (bind most loosely)
First-order variants of t-norm logics employ the usual logical language of first-order logic with the above propositional connectives and the following quantifiers:
The first-order variant of a propositional t-norm logic
is usually denoted by
Semantics
Algebraic semantics is predominantly used for propositional t-norm fuzzy logics, with three main classes of algebras with respect to which a t-norm fuzzy logic
is
complete:
- General semantics, formed of all
-algebras
— that is, all algebras for which the logic is sound.- Linear semantics, formed of all linear
-algebras — that is, all
-algebras whose
lattice order is
linear.
- Standard semantics, formed of all standard
-algebras — that is, all
-algebras whose lattice reduct is the real unit interval [0, 1] with the usual order. In standard
-algebras, the interpretation of strong conjunction is a left-continuous
t-norm and the interpretation of most propositional connectives is determined by the t-norm (hence the names
t-norm-based logics and
t-norm
-algebras, which is also used for
-algebras on the lattice [0, 1]). In t-norm logics with additional connectives, however, the real-valued interpretation of the additional connectives may be restricted by further conditions for the t-norm algebra to be called standard: for example, in standard
-algebras of the logic
with involution, the interpretation of the additional involutive negation
is required to be the
standard involution
rather than other involutions that can also interpret
over t-norm
-algebras.
[10] In general, therefore, the definition of standard t-norm algebras has to be explicitly given for t-norm logics with additional connectives.
Bibliography
- Esteva F. & Godo L., 2001, "Monoidal t-norm based logic: Towards a logic of left-continuous t-norms". Fuzzy Sets and Systems 124: 271–288.
- Flaminio T. & Marchioni E., 2006, T-norm based logics with an independent involutive negation. Fuzzy Sets and Systems 157: 3125–3144.
- Gottwald S. & Hájek P., 2005, Triangular norm based mathematical fuzzy logic. In E.P. Klement & R. Mesiar (eds.), Logical, Algebraic, Analytic and Probabilistic Aspects of Triangular Norms, pp. 275–300. Elsevier, Amsterdam 2005.
- Hájek P., 1998, Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer. .
References
- Esteva & Godo (2001)
- Łukasiewicz J., 1920, O logice trojwartosciowej (Polish, On three-valued logic). Ruch filozoficzny 5:170–171.
- Hay, L.S., 1963, Axiomatization of the infinite-valued predicate calculus. Journal of Symbolic Logic 28:77–86.
- Gödel K., 1932, Zum intuitionistischen Aussagenkalkül, Anzeiger Akademie der Wissenschaften Wien 69: 65–66.
- Dummett M., 1959, Propositional calculus with denumerable matrix, Journal of Symbolic Logic 27: 97–106
- Esteva F., Godo L., & Montagna F., 2001, The ŁΠ and ŁΠ½ logics: Two complete fuzzy systems joining Łukasiewicz and product logics, Archive for Mathematical Logic 40: 39–67.
- Cintula P., 2001, The ŁΠ and ŁΠ½ propositional and predicate logics, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 124: 289–302.
- Baaz M., 1996, Infinite-valued Gödel logic with 0-1-projections and relativisations. In P. Hájek (ed.), Gödel'96: Logical Foundations of Mathematics, Computer Science, and Physics, Springer, Lecture Notes in Logic 6: 23–33
- Hájek (1998)
- Flaminio & Marchioni (2006)