Finite intersection property explained
is said to have the
finite intersection property (FIP) if the
intersection over any finite subcollection of
is
non-empty. It has the
strong finite intersection property (SFIP) if the intersection over any finite subcollection of
is infinite. Sets with the finite intersection property are also called
centered systems and
filter subbases.
The finite intersection property can be used to reformulate topological compactness in terms of closed sets; this is its most prominent application. Other applications include proving that certain perfect sets are uncountable, and the construction of ultrafilters.
Definition
Let be a set and a nonempty family of subsets of that is, is a subset of the power set of Then is said to have the finite intersection property if every nonempty finite subfamily has nonempty intersection; it is said to have the strong finite intersection property if that intersection is always infinite.
In symbols, has the FIP if, for any choice of a finite nonempty subset of there must exist a point Likewise, has the SFIP if, for every choice of such there are infinitely many such
In the study of filters, the common intersection of a family of sets is called a kernel, from much the same etymology as the sunflower. Families with empty kernel are called free; those with nonempty kernel, fixed.
Families of examples and non-examples
The empty set cannot belong to any collection with the finite intersection property.
A sufficient condition for the FIP intersection property is a nonempty kernel. The converse is generally false, but holds for finite families; that is, if
is finite, then
has the finite intersection property if and only if it is fixed.
Pairwise intersection
The finite intersection property is strictly stronger than pairwise intersection; the family
\{\{1,2\},\{2,3\},\{1,3\}\}
has pairwise intersections, but not the FIP.
More generally, let be a positive integer greater than unity, and Then any subset of
with fewer than
elements has nonempty intersection, but
lacks the FIP.
End-type constructions
If
A1\supseteqA2\supseteqA3 …
is a decreasing sequence of non-empty sets, then the family
has the finite intersection property (and is even a
–system). If the inclusions
A1\supseteqA2\supseteqA3 …
are
strict, then
admits the strong finite intersection property as well.
More generally, any that is totally ordered by inclusion has the FIP.
At the same time, the kernel of may be empty: if then the kernel of
is the
empty set. Similarly, the family of intervals
\left\{[r,infty):r\in\R\right\}
also has the (S)FIP, but empty kernel.
"Generic" sets and properties
The family of all Borel subsets of
with
Lebesgue measure has the FIP, as does the family of
comeagre sets. If
is an infinite set, then the
Fréchet filter (the family has the FIP. All of these are free filters; they are upwards-closed and have empty infinitary intersection.
If
and, for each positive integer
the subset
is precisely all elements of
having
digit
in the
th decimal place, then any finite intersection of
is non-empty — just take
in those finitely many places and
in the rest. But the intersection of
for all
is empty, since no element of
has all zero digits.
Extension of the ground set
The (strong) finite intersection property is a characteristic of the family not the ground set If a family on the set admits the (S)FIP and then is also a family on the set with the FIP (resp. SFIP).
Generated filters and topologies
If
are sets with
then the family
l{A}=\{S\subseteqX:K\subseteqS\}
has the FIP; this family is called the principal filter on
generated by The subset
l{B}=\{I\subseteq\R:K\subseteqIandIanopeninterval\}
has the FIP for much the same reason: the kernels contain the non-empty set If
is an open interval, then the set
is in fact equal to the kernels of
or and so is an element of each filter. But in general a filter's kernel need not be an element of the filter.
A proper filter on a set has the finite intersection property. Every neighbourhood subbasis at a point in a topological space has the FIP, and the same is true of every neighbourhood basis and every neighbourhood filter at a point (because each is, in particular, also a neighbourhood subbasis).
Relationship to -systems and filters
See main article: Pi-system. A –system is a non-empty family of sets that is closed under finite intersections. The set of all finite intersections of one or more sets from
is called the
–system generated by because it is the
smallest –system having
as a subset.
The upward closure of
in
is the set
For any family the finite intersection property is equivalent to any of the following:
- The –system generated by
does not have the empty set as an element; that is,
\varnothing\notin\pi(l{A}).
- The set
has the finite intersection property.
- The set
is a (proper)[1] prefilter.
- The family
is a subset of some (proper) prefilter.
- The upward closure is a (proper) filter on In this case,
is called the filter on generated by because it is the minimal (with respect to
) filter on
that contains
as a subset.
-
is a subset of some (proper) filter.
Applications
Compactness
The finite intersection property is useful in formulating an alternative definition of compactness:
This formulation of compactness is used in some proofs of Tychonoff's theorem.
Uncountability of perfect spaces
Another common application is to prove that the real numbers are uncountable. All the conditions in the statement of the theorem are necessary:
- We cannot eliminate the Hausdorff condition; a countable set (with at least two points) with the indiscrete topology is compact, has more than one point, and satisfies the property that no one point sets are open, but is not uncountable.
- We cannot eliminate the compactness condition, as the set of rational numbers shows.
- We cannot eliminate the condition that one point sets cannot be open, as any finite space with the discrete topology shows.
Ultrafilters
Let
be non-empty,
having the finite intersection property. Then there exists an
ultrafilter (in
) such that
This result is known as the ultrafilter lemma.
[2] References
General sources
- Koutras. Costas D.. Moyzes. Christos. Nomikos. Christos. Tsaprounis. Konstantinos. Zikos. Yorgos. On Weak Filters and Ultrafilters: Set Theory From (and for) Knowledge Representation. Logic Journal of the IGPL. 20 October 2021. 10.1093/jigpal/jzab030.
- Web site: MacIver R.. David. Filters in Analysis and Topology. 1 July 2004. https://web.archive.org/web/20071009170540/http://www.efnet-math.org/~david/mathematics/filters.pdf . 2007-10-09 . (Provides an introductory review of filters in topology and in metric spaces.)
Notes and References
- A filter or prefilter on a set is or if it does not contain the empty set as an element. Like many − but not all − authors, this article will require non-degeneracy as part of the definitions of "prefilter" and "filter".
- .