Finite intersection property explained

X

is said to have the finite intersection property (FIP) if the intersection over any finite subcollection of

A

is non-empty. It has the strong finite intersection property (SFIP) if the intersection over any finite subcollection of

A

is infinite. Sets with the finite intersection property are also called centered systems and filter subbases.

The finite intersection property can be used to reformulate topological compactness in terms of closed sets; this is its most prominent application. Other applications include proving that certain perfect sets are uncountable, and the construction of ultrafilters.

Definition

Let X be a set and \mathcal a nonempty family of subsets of that is, \mathcal is a subset of the power set of Then \mathcal is said to have the finite intersection property if every nonempty finite subfamily has nonempty intersection; it is said to have the strong finite intersection property if that intersection is always infinite.

In symbols, \mathcal has the FIP if, for any choice of a finite nonempty subset \mathcal of there must exist a point x\in\bigcap_\text Likewise, \mathcal has the SFIP if, for every choice of such there are infinitely many such

In the study of filters, the common intersection of a family of sets is called a kernel, from much the same etymology as the sunflower. Families with empty kernel are called free; those with nonempty kernel, fixed.

Families of examples and non-examples

The empty set cannot belong to any collection with the finite intersection property.

A sufficient condition for the FIP intersection property is a nonempty kernel. The converse is generally false, but holds for finite families; that is, if

l{A}

is finite, then

l{A}

has the finite intersection property if and only if it is fixed.

Pairwise intersection

The finite intersection property is strictly stronger than pairwise intersection; the family

\{\{1,2\},\{2,3\},\{1,3\}\}

has pairwise intersections, but not the FIP.

More generally, let n \in \N\setminus\ be a positive integer greater than unity, and Then any subset of

l{A}

with fewer than n elements has nonempty intersection, but \mathcal lacks the FIP.

End-type constructions

If

A1\supseteqA2\supseteqA3

is a decreasing sequence of non-empty sets, then the family \mathcal = \left\ has the finite intersection property (and is even a –system). If the inclusions

A1\supseteqA2\supseteqA3

are strict, then \mathcal admits the strong finite intersection property as well.

More generally, any \mathcal that is totally ordered by inclusion has the FIP.

At the same time, the kernel of \mathcal may be empty: if then the kernel of

l{A}

is the empty set. Similarly, the family of intervals

\left\{[r,infty):r\in\R\right\}

also has the (S)FIP, but empty kernel.

"Generic" sets and properties

The family of all Borel subsets of

[0,1]

with Lebesgue measure 1 has the FIP, as does the family of comeagre sets. If X is an infinite set, then the Fréchet filter (the family has the FIP. All of these are free filters; they are upwards-closed and have empty infinitary intersection.

If

X=(0,1)

and, for each positive integer

i,

the subset

Xi

is precisely all elements of

X

having digit

0

in the

i

th decimal place, then any finite intersection of

Xi

is non-empty — just take

0

in those finitely many places and

1

in the rest. But the intersection of

Xi

for all

i\geq1

is empty, since no element of

(0,1)

has all zero digits.

Extension of the ground set

The (strong) finite intersection property is a characteristic of the family not the ground set If a family \mathcal on the set X admits the (S)FIP and then \mathcal is also a family on the set Y with the FIP (resp. SFIP).

Generated filters and topologies

If

K\subseteqX

are sets with

K\varnothing

then the family

l{A}=\{S\subseteqX:K\subseteqS\}

has the FIP; this family is called the principal filter on X generated by The subset

l{B}=\{I\subseteq\R:K\subseteqIandIanopeninterval\}

has the FIP for much the same reason: the kernels contain the non-empty set If K is an open interval, then the set K is in fact equal to the kernels of \mathcal or and so is an element of each filter. But in general a filter's kernel need not be an element of the filter.

A proper filter on a set has the finite intersection property. Every neighbourhood subbasis at a point in a topological space has the FIP, and the same is true of every neighbourhood basis and every neighbourhood filter at a point (because each is, in particular, also a neighbourhood subbasis).

Relationship to -systems and filters

See main article: Pi-system. A –system is a non-empty family of sets that is closed under finite intersections. The set \pi(\mathcal) = \left\of all finite intersections of one or more sets from

l{A}

is called the –system generated by because it is the smallest –system having \mathcal as a subset.

The upward closure of

\pi(l{A})

in X is the set \pi(\mathcal)^ = \left\\text

For any family the finite intersection property is equivalent to any of the following:

Applications

Compactness

The finite intersection property is useful in formulating an alternative definition of compactness:

This formulation of compactness is used in some proofs of Tychonoff's theorem.

Uncountability of perfect spaces

Another common application is to prove that the real numbers are uncountable. All the conditions in the statement of the theorem are necessary:

  1. We cannot eliminate the Hausdorff condition; a countable set (with at least two points) with the indiscrete topology is compact, has more than one point, and satisfies the property that no one point sets are open, but is not uncountable.
  2. We cannot eliminate the compactness condition, as the set of rational numbers shows.
  3. We cannot eliminate the condition that one point sets cannot be open, as any finite space with the discrete topology shows.

Ultrafilters

Let

X

be non-empty,

F\subseteq2X.

F

having the finite intersection property. Then there exists an

U

ultrafilter (in

2X

) such that

F\subseteqU.

This result is known as the ultrafilter lemma.[2]

References

General sources

Notes and References

  1. A filter or prefilter on a set is or if it does not contain the empty set as an element. Like many − but not all − authors, this article will require non-degeneracy as part of the definitions of "prefilter" and "filter".
  2. .