Stationary set explained

In mathematics, specifically set theory and model theory, a stationary set is a set that is not too small in the sense that it intersects all club sets and is analogous to a set of non-zero measure in measure theory. There are at least three closely related notions of stationary set, depending on whether one is looking at subsets of an ordinal, or subsets of something of given cardinality, or a powerset.

Classical notion

If

\kappa

is a cardinal of uncountable cofinality,

S\subseteq\kappa,

and

S

intersects every club set in

\kappa,

then

S

is called a stationary set.[1] If a set is not stationary, then it is called a thin set. This notion should not be confused with the notion of a thin set in number theory.

If

S

is a stationary set and

C

is a club set, then their intersection

S\capC

is also stationary. This is because if

D

is any club set, then

C\capD

is a club set, thus

(S\capC)\capD=S\cap(C\capD)

is nonempty. Therefore,

(S\capC)

must be stationary.

See also: Fodor's lemma

The restriction to uncountable cofinality is in order to avoid trivialities: Suppose

\kappa

has countable cofinality. Then

S\subseteq\kappa

is stationary in

\kappa

if and only if

\kappa\setminusS

is bounded in

\kappa

. In particular, if the cofinality of

\kappa

is

\omega=\aleph0

, then any two stationary subsets of

\kappa

have stationary intersection.

This is no longer the case if the cofinality of

\kappa

is uncountable. In fact, suppose

\kappa

is moreover regular and

S\subseteq\kappa

is stationary. Then

S

can be partitioned into

\kappa

many disjoint stationary sets. This result is due to Solovay. If

\kappa

is a successor cardinal, this result is due to Ulam and is easily shown by means of what is called an Ulam matrix.

H. Friedman has shown that for every countable successor ordinal

\beta

, every stationary subset of

\omega1

contains a closed subset of order type

\beta

.

Jech's notion

There is also a notion of stationary subset of

[X]λ

, for

λ

a cardinal and

X

a set such that

|X|\geλ

, where

[X]λ

is the set of subsets of

X

of cardinality

λ

:

[X]λ=\{Y\subseteqX:|Y|\}

. This notion is due to Thomas Jech. As before,

S\subseteq[X]λ

is stationary if and only if it meets every club, where a club subset of

[X]λ

is a set unbounded under

\subseteq

and closed under union of chains of length at most

λ

. These notions are in general different, although for

X=\omega1

and

λ=\aleph0

they coincide in the sense that
\omega
S\subseteq[\omega
1]
is stationary if and only if

S\cap\omega1

is stationary in

\omega1

.

The appropriate version of Fodor's lemma also holds for this notion.

Generalized notion

There is yet a third notion, model theoretic in nature and sometimes referred to as generalized stationarity. This notion is probably due to Magidor, Foreman and Shelah and has also been used prominently by Woodin.

Now let

X

be a nonempty set. A set

C\subseteq{lP}(X)

is club (closed and unbounded) if and only if there is a function

F:[X]<\omega\toX

such that

C=\{z:F[[z]<\omega]\subseteqz\}

. Here,

[y]<\omega

is the collection of finite subsets of

y

.

S\subseteq{lP}(X)

is stationary in

{lP}(X)

if and only if it meets every club subset of

{lP}(X)

.

To see the connection with model theory, notice that if

M

is a structure with universe

X

in a countable language and

F

is a Skolem function for

M

, then a stationary

S

must contain an elementary substructure of

M

. In fact,

S\subseteq{lP}(X)

is stationary if and only if for any such structure

M

there is an elementary substructure of

M

that belongs to

S

.

References

Notes and References

  1. Jech (2003) p.91