In mathematics, set-theoretic topology is a subject that combines set theory and general topology. It focuses on topological questions that are independent of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC).
See main article: article and Dowker space.
In the mathematical field of general topology, a Dowker space is a topological space that is T4 but not countably paracompact.
\aleph0 | |
\aleph | |
\omega |
\aleph\omega+1
A famous problem is the normal Moore space question, a question in general topology that was the subject of intense research. The answer to the normal Moore space question was eventually proved to be independent of ZFC.
See main article: article and Cardinal function.
Cardinal functions are widely used in topology as a tool for describing various topological properties.[4] [5] Below are some examples. (Note: some authors, arguing that "there are no finite cardinal numbers in general topology",[6] prefer to define the cardinal functions listed below so that they never take on finite cardinal numbers as values; this requires modifying some of the definitions given below, e.g. by adding "
+ \aleph0
\le\aleph0
\pi
\pi
\pi
\chi(X)=\sup \{\chi(x,X):x\inX\}.
When
\chi(X)\le\aleph0
\rm{d}(X)\le\aleph0
\rm{L}(X)=\aleph0
{\rmc}(X)=\sup\{|{lU}|:{lU}
X\}
s(X)={\rmhc}(X)=\sup\{{\rmc}(Y):Y\subseteqX\}
or
s(X)=\sup\{|Y|:Y\subseteqX
\}
x\inX
\alpha
x\in{\rmcl}X(Y)
\alpha
x\in{\rmcl}X(Z)
t(x,X)=\sup\{min\{|Z|:Z\subseteqY \wedge x\in{\rmcl}X(Z)\}:Y\subseteqX \wedge x\in{\rmcl}X(Y)\}.
The tightness of a space X is
t(X)=\sup\{t(x,X):x\inX\}
\aleph0
t+(X)
\alpha
Y\subseteqX
x\in{\rmcl}X(Y)
\alpha
x\in{\rmcl}X(Z)
See main article: article and Martin's axiom.
For any cardinal k, we define a statement, denoted by MA(k):
For any partial order P satisfying the countable chain condition (hereafter ccc) and any family D of dense sets in P such that |D| ≤ k, there is a filter F on P such that F ∩ d is non-empty for every d in D.
Since it is a theorem of ZFC that MA(c) fails, Martin's axiom is stated as:
Martin's axiom (MA): For every k < c, MA(k) holds.
In this case (for application of ccc), an antichain is a subset A of P such that any two distinct members of A are incompatible (two elements are said to be compatible if there exists a common element below both of them in the partial order). This differs from, for example, the notion of antichain in the context of trees.
MA(
\aleph0 | |
2 |
\aleph0 | |
2 |
An equivalent formulation is: If X is a compact Hausdorff topological space which satisfies the ccc then X is not the union of k or fewer nowhere dense subsets.
Martin's axiom has a number of other interesting combinatorial, analytic and topological consequences:
\aleph1
See main article: Forcing (mathematics). Forcing is a technique invented by Paul Cohen for proving consistency and independence results. It was first used, in 1963, to prove the independence of the axiom of choice and the continuum hypothesis from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. Forcing was considerably reworked and simplified in the 1960s, and has proven to be an extremely powerful technique both within set theory and in areas of mathematical logic such as recursion theory.
Intuitively, forcing consists of expanding the set theoretical universe V to a larger universe V*. In this bigger universe, for example, one might have many new subsets of ω = that were not there in the old universe, and thereby violate the continuum hypothesis. While impossible on the face of it, this is just another version of Cantor's paradox about infinity. In principle, one could consider
V*=V x \{0,1\},
identify
x\inV
(x,0)
(x,1)
See the main articles for applications such as random reals.
\aleph\omega+1
. István Juhász (mathematician). Cardinal functions in topology . Math. Centre Tracts, Amsterdam . 1979 . 90-6196-062-2 .
. Ryszard Engelking . General Topology . Heldermann Verlag, Berlin . 1989 . 3885380064 .