In physics, canonical quantization is a procedure for quantizing a classical theory, while attempting to preserve the formal structure, such as symmetries, of the classical theory to the greatest extent possible.
Historically, this was not quite Werner Heisenberg's route to obtaining quantum mechanics, but Paul Dirac introduced it in his 1926 doctoral thesis, the "method of classical analogy" for quantization,[1] and detailed it in his classic text Principles of Quantum Mechanics.[2] The word canonical arises from the Hamiltonian approach to classical mechanics, in which a system's dynamics is generated via canonical Poisson brackets, a structure which is only partially preserved in canonical quantization.
This method was further used by Paul Dirac in the context of quantum field theory, in his construction of quantum electrodynamics. In the field theory context, it is also called the second quantization of fields, in contrast to the semi-classical first quantization of single particles.
When it was first developed, quantum physics dealt only with the quantization of the motion of particles, leaving the electromagnetic field classical, hence the name quantum mechanics.[3]
Later the electromagnetic field was also quantized, and even the particles themselves became represented through quantized fields, resulting in the development of quantum electrodynamics (QED) and quantum field theory in general.[4] Thus, by convention, the original form of particle quantum mechanics is denoted first quantization, while quantum field theory is formulated in the language of second quantization.
See main article: First quantization.
The following exposition is based on Dirac's treatise on quantum mechanics.[2] In the classical mechanics of a particle, there are dynamic variables which are called coordinates and momenta . These specify the state of a classical system. The canonical structure (also known as the symplectic structure) of classical mechanics consists of Poisson brackets enclosing these variables, such as . All transformations of variables which preserve these brackets are allowed as canonical transformations in classical mechanics. Motion itself is such a canonical transformation.
By contrast, in quantum mechanics, all significant features of a particle are contained in a state
|\psi\rangle
The eigenvalue of an operator acting on one of its eigenstates represents the value of a measurement on the particle thus represented. For example, the energy is read off by the Hamiltonian operator
\hat{H}
|\psin\rangle
|\psin\rangle
Any state could be represented as a linear combination of eigenstates of energy; for example,where are constant coefficients.
As in classical mechanics, all dynamical operators can be represented by functions of the position and momentum ones,
\hat{X}
\hat{P}
\hat{X}
x
|x\rangle
\hat{X}|x\rangle=x|x\rangle
\psi(x)=\langlex|\psi\rangle
Likewise, the eigenstates
|p\rangle
\hat{P}
\psi(p)=\langlep|\psi\rangle
The central relation between these operators is a quantum analog of the above Poisson bracket of classical mechanics, the canonical commutation relation,
This relation encodes (and formally leads to) the uncertainty principle, in the form . This algebraic structure may be thus considered as the quantum analog of the canonical structure of classical mechanics.
When turning to N-particle systems, i.e., systems containing N identical particles (particles characterized by the same quantum numbers such as mass, charge and spin), it is necessary to extend the single-particle state function
\psi(r)
\psi(r1,r2,...,rN)
where we have interchanged two coordinates
(rj,rk)
Dirac's book[2] details his popular rule of supplanting Poisson brackets by commutators:
One might interpret this proposal as saying that we should seek a "quantization map"
Q
f
Qf
f
One concrete version of the above impossibility claim is Groenewold's theorem (after Dutch theoretical physicist Hilbrand J. Groenewold), which we describe for a system with one degree of freedom for simplicity. Let us accept the following "ground rules" for the map
Q
Q
Q
x
p
X
P
Q
x
p
X
P
X
P
f
g
Actually, the nonexistence of such a map occurs already by the time we reach polynomials of degree four. Note that the Poisson bracket of two polynomials of degree four has degree six, so it does not exactly make sense to require a map on polynomials of degree four to respect the bracket condition. We can, however, require that the bracket condition holds when
f
g
The proof can be outlined as follows.[6] [7] Suppose we first try to find a quantization map on polynomials of degree less than or equal to three satisfying the bracket condition whenever
f
g
The argument is finished by computing by brute force thatdoes not coincide withThus, we have two incompatible requirements for the value of
Q(x2p2)
If represents the quantization map that acts on functions in classical phase space, then the following properties are usually considered desirable:[8]
Qx\psi=x\psi
Qp\psi=-i\hbar\partialx\psi~~
f\longmapstoQf~~
[Qf,Qg]=i\hbarQ\{f,g\
Qg=g(Qf)~~
However, not only are these four properties mutually inconsistent, any three of them are also inconsistent![9] As it turns out, the only pairs of these properties that lead to self-consistent, nontrivial solutions are 2 & 3, and possibly 1 & 3 or 1 & 4. Accepting properties 1 & 2, along with a weaker condition that 3 be true only asymptotically in the limit (see Moyal bracket), leads to deformation quantization, and some extraneous information must be provided, as in the standard theories utilized in most of physics. Accepting properties 1 & 2 & 3 but restricting the space of quantizable observables to exclude terms such as the cubic ones in the above example amounts to geometric quantization.
See main article: Second quantization. Quantum mechanics was successful at describing non-relativistic systems with fixed numbers of particles, but a new framework was needed to describe systems in which particles can be created or destroyed, for example, the electromagnetic field, considered as a collection of photons. It was eventually realized that special relativity was inconsistent with single-particle quantum mechanics, so that all particles are now described relativistically by quantum fields.
When the canonical quantization procedure is applied to a field, such as the electromagnetic field, the classical field variables become quantum operators. Thus, the normal modes comprising the amplitude of the field are simple oscillators, each of which is quantized in standard first quantization, above, without ambiguity. The resulting quanta are identified with individual particles or excitations. For example, the quanta of the electromagnetic field are identified with photons. Unlike first quantization, conventional second quantization is completely unambiguous, in effect a functor, since the constituent set of its oscillators are quantized unambiguously.
Historically, quantizing the classical theory of a single particle gave rise to a wavefunction. The classical equations of motion of a field are typically identical in form to the (quantum) equations for the wave-function of one of its quanta. For example, the Klein–Gordon equation is the classical equation of motion for a free scalar field, but also the quantum equation for a scalar particle wave-function. This meant that quantizing a field appeared to be similar to quantizing a theory that was already quantized, leading to the fanciful term second quantization in the early literature, which is still used to describe field quantization, even though the modern interpretation detailed is different.
One drawback to canonical quantization for a relativistic field is that by relying on the Hamiltonian to determine time dependence, relativistic invariance is no longer manifest. Thus it is necessary to check that relativistic invariance is not lost. Alternatively, the Feynman integral approach is available for quantizing relativistic fields, and is manifestly invariant. For non-relativistic field theories, such as those used in condensed matter physics, Lorentz invariance is not an issue.
Quantum mechanically, the variables of a field (such as the field's amplitude at a given point) are represented by operators on a Hilbert space. In general, all observables are constructed as operators on the Hilbert space, and the time-evolution of the operators is governed by the Hamiltonian, which must be a positive operator. A state
|0\rangle
A scalar field theory provides a good example of the canonical quantization procedure.[10] Classically, a scalar field is a collection of an infinity of oscillator normal modes. It suffices to consider a 1+1-dimensional space-time
R x S1,
The classical Lagrangian density describes an infinity of coupled harmonic oscillators, labelled by which is now a label (and not the displacement dynamical variable to be quantized), denoted by the classical field,where is a potential term, often taken to be a polynomial or monomial of degree 3 or higher. The action functional isThe canonical momentum obtained via the Legendre transformation using the action is
\pi=\partialt\phi
Canonical quantization treats the variables and as operators with canonical commutation relations at time = 0, given byOperators constructed from and can then formally be defined at other times via the time-evolution generated by the Hamiltonian,
However, since and no longer commute, this expression is ambiguous at the quantum level. The problem is to construct a representation of the relevant operators
l{O}
l{H}
l{O}
l{H}
|0\rangle
In the case of a free field, with, the quantization procedure is relatively straightforward. It is convenient to Fourier transform the fields, so thatThe reality of the fields implies thatThe classical Hamiltonian may be expanded in Fourier modes aswhere
\omegak=\sqrt{k2+m2}
This Hamiltonian is thus recognizable as an infinite sum of classical normal mode oscillator excitations, each one of which is quantized in the standard manner, so the free quantum Hamiltonian looks identical. It is the s that have become operators obeying the standard commutation relations,, with all others vanishing. The collective Hilbert space of all these oscillators is thus constructed using creation and annihilation operators constructed from these modes,for which for all, with all other commutators vanishing.
The vacuum
|0\rangle
l{H}
|0\rangle
This Hamiltonian differs from the previous expression by the subtraction of the zero-point energy of each harmonic oscillator. This satisfies the condition that must annihilate the vacuum, without affecting the time-evolution of operators via the above exponentiation operation. This subtraction of the zero-point energy may be considered to be a resolution of the quantum operator ordering ambiguity, since it is equivalent to requiring that all creation operators appear to the left of annihilation operators in the expansion of the Hamiltonian. This procedure is known as Wick ordering or normal ordering.
All other fields can be quantized by a generalization of this procedure. Vector or tensor fields simply have more components, and independent creation and destruction operators must be introduced for each independent component. If a field has any internal symmetry, then creation and destruction operators must be introduced for each component of the field related to this symmetry as well. If there is a gauge symmetry, then the number of independent components of the field must be carefully analyzed to avoid over-counting equivalent configurations, and gauge-fixing may be applied if needed.
It turns out that commutation relations are useful only for quantizing bosons, for which the occupancy number of any state is unlimited. To quantize fermions, which satisfy the Pauli exclusion principle, anti-commutators are needed. These are defined by .
When quantizing fermions, the fields are expanded in creation and annihilation operators,,, which satisfy
The states are constructed on a vacuum
|0\rangle
\dagger) | |
(\theta | |
k |
2|0\rangle=0
The construction of the scalar field states above assumed that the potential was minimized at = 0, so that the vacuum minimizing the Hamiltonian satisfies, indicating that the vacuum expectation value (VEV) of the field is zero. In cases involving spontaneous symmetry breaking, it is possible to have a non-zero VEV, because the potential is minimized for a value = . This occurs for example, if with and, for which the minimum energy is found at . The value of in one of these vacua may be considered as condensate of the field . Canonical quantization then can be carried out for the shifted field, and particle states with respect to the shifted vacuum are defined by quantizing the shifted field. This construction is utilized in the Higgs mechanism in the standard model of particle physics.
The classical theory is described using a spacelike foliation of spacetime with the state at each slice being described by an element of a symplectic manifold with the time evolution given by the symplectomorphism generated by a Hamiltonian function over the symplectic manifold. The quantum algebra of "operators" is an -deformation of the algebra of smooth functions over the symplectic space such that the leading term in the Taylor expansion over of the commutator expressed in the phase space formulation is . (Here, the curly braces denote the Poisson bracket. The subleading terms are all encoded in the Moyal bracket, the suitable quantum deformation of the Poisson bracket.) In general, for the quantities (observables) involved,and providing the arguments of such brackets, ħ-deformations are highly nonunique—quantization is an "art", and is specified by the physical context.(Two different quantum systems may represent two different, inequivalent, deformations of the same classical limit, .)
Now, one looks for unitary representations of this quantum algebra. With respect to such a unitary representation, a symplectomorphism in the classical theory would now deform to a (metaplectic) unitary transformation. In particular, the time evolution symplectomorphism generated by the classical Hamiltonian deforms to a unitary transformation generated by the corresponding quantum Hamiltonian.
A further generalization is to consider a Poisson manifold instead of a symplectic space for the classical theory and perform an ħ-deformation of the corresponding Poisson algebra or even Poisson supermanifolds.
See main article: Geometric quantization. In contrast to the theory of deformation quantization described above, geometric quantization seeks to construct an actual Hilbert space and operators on it. Starting with a symplectic manifold
M
M
M
One then proceeds by choosing a polarization, that is (roughly), a choice of
n
2n
n
n
QED and the men who made it, Princeton Univ. Press, 1994,