Scientific evidence explained
Scientific evidence is evidence that serves to either support or counter a scientific theory or hypothesis,[1] although scientists also use evidence in other ways, such as when applying theories to practical problems.[2] Such evidence is expected to be empirical evidence and interpretable in accordance with the scientific method. Standards for scientific evidence vary according to the field of inquiry, but the strength of scientific evidence is generally based on the results of statistical analysis and the strength of scientific controls.
Principles of inference
A person's assumptions or beliefs about the relationship between observations and a hypothesis will affect whether that person takes the observations as evidence.[3] These assumptions or beliefs will also affect how a person utilizes the observations as evidence. For example, the Earth's apparent lack of motion may be taken as evidence for a geocentric cosmology. However, after sufficient evidence is presented for heliocentric cosmology and the apparent lack of motion is explained, the initial observation is strongly discounted as evidence.
When rational observers have different background beliefs, they may draw different conclusions from the same scientific evidence. For example, Priestley, working with phlogiston theory, explained his observations about the decomposition of mercuric oxide using phlogiston. In contrast, Lavoisier, developing the theory of elements, explained the same observations with reference to oxygen.[4] A causal relationship between the observations and hypothesis does not exist to cause the observation to be taken as evidence,[3] but rather the causal relationship is provided by the person seeking to establish observations as evidence.
A more formal method to characterize the effect of background beliefs is Bayesian inference.[5] In Bayesian inference, beliefs are expressed as percentages indicating one's confidence in them. One starts from an initial probability (a prior), and then updates that probability using Bayes' theorem after observing evidence.[6] As a result, two independent observers of the same event will rationally arrive at different conclusions if their priors (previous observations that are also relevant to the conclusion) differ.
The importance of background beliefs in the determination of what observations are evidence can be illustrated using deductive reasoning, such as syllogisms.[7] If either of the propositions is not accepted as true, the conclusion will not be accepted either.
Utility of scientific evidence
See also: Falsifiability.
Philosophers, such as Karl R. Popper, have provided influential theories of the scientific method within which scientific evidence plays a central role.[8] In summary, Popper provides that a scientist creatively develops a theory that may be falsified by testing the theory against evidence or known facts. Popper's theory presents an asymmetry in that evidence can prove a theory wrong, by establishing facts that are inconsistent with the theory. In contrast, evidence cannot prove a theory correct because other evidence, yet to be discovered, may exist that is inconsistent with the theory.[9]
Philosophical versus scientific views
In the 20th century, many philosophers investigated the logical relationship between evidence statements and hypotheses, whereas scientists tended to focus on how the data used for statistical inference are generated.[10] But according to philosopher Deborah Mayo, by the end of the 20th century philosophers had come to understand that "there are key features of scientific practice that are overlooked or misdescribed by all such logical accounts of evidence, whether hypothetico-deductive, Bayesian, or instantiationist".[10]
There were a variety of 20th-century philosophical approaches to decide whether an observation may be considered evidence; many of these focused on the relationship between the evidence and the hypothesis. In the 1950s, Rudolf Carnap recommended distinguishing such approaches into three categories: classificatory (whether the evidence confirms the hypothesis), comparative (whether the evidence supports a first hypothesis more than an alternative hypothesis) or quantitative (the degree to which the evidence supports a hypothesis).[11] A 1983 anthology edited by Peter Achinstein provided a concise presentation by prominent philosophers on scientific evidence, including Carl Hempel (on the logic of confirmation), R. B. Braithwaite (on the structure of a scientific system), Norwood Russell Hanson (on the logic of discovery), Nelson Goodman (of grue fame, on a theory of projection), Rudolf Carnap (on the concept of confirming evidence), Wesley C. Salmon (on confirmation and relevance), and Clark Glymour (on relevant evidence).[12] In 1990, William Bechtel provided four factors (clarity of the data, replication by others, consistency with results arrived at by alternative methods, and consistency with plausible theories of mechanisms) that biologists used to settle controversies about procedures and reliability of evidence.[13]
In 2001, Achinstein published his own book on the subject titled The Book of Evidence, in which, among other topics, he distinguished between four concepts of evidence: epistemic-situation evidence (evidence relative to a given epistemic situation), subjective evidence (considered to be evidence by a particular person at a particular time), veridical evidence (a good reason to believe that a hypothesis is true), and potential evidence (a good reason to believe that a hypothesis is highly probable).[14] Achinstein defined all his concepts of evidence in terms of potential evidence, since any other kind of evidence must at least be potential evidence, and he argued that scientists mainly seek veridical evidence but they also use the other concepts of evidence, which rely on a distinctive concept of probability, and Achinstein contrasted this concept of probability with previous probabilistic theories of evidence such as Bayesian, Carnapian, and frequentist.[14]
Simplicity is one common philosophical criterion for scientific theories.[15] Based on the philosophical assumption of the strong Church-Turing thesis, a mathematical criterion for evaluation of evidence has been conjectured, with the criterion having a resemblance to the idea of Occam's razor that the simplest comprehensive description of the evidence is most likely correct. It states formally, "The ideal principle states that the prior probability associated with the hypothesis should be given by the algorithmic universal probability, and the sum of the log universal probability of the model plus the log of the probability of the data given the model should be minimized."[16] However, some philosophers (including Richard Boyd, Mario Bunge, John D. Norton, and Elliott Sober) have adopted a skeptical or deflationary view of the role of simplicity in science, arguing in various ways that its importance has been overemphasized.[17]
Emphasis on hypothesis testing as the essence of science is prevalent among both scientists and philosophers.[18] However, philosophers have noted that testing hypotheses by confronting them with new evidence does not account for all the ways that scientists use evidence.[2] For example, when Geiger and Marsden scattered alpha particles through thin gold foil, the resulting data enabled their experimental adviser, Ernest Rutherford, to very accurately calculate the mass and size of an atomic nucleus for the first time. Rutherford used the data to develop a new atomic model, not only to test an existing hypothesis; such use of evidence to produce new hypotheses is sometimes called abduction (following C. S. Peirce).[19] Social-science methodologist Donald T. Campbell, who emphasized hypothesis testing throughout his career, later increasingly emphasized that the essence of science is "not experimentation per se" but instead the iterative competition of "plausible rival hypotheses", a process that at any given phase may start from evidence or may start from hypothesis.[20] Other scientists and philosophers have emphasized the central role of questions and problems in the use of data and hypotheses.[21]
Concept of scientific proof
While the phrase "scientific proof" is often used in the popular media,[22] many scientists and philosophers have argued that there is really no such thing as infallible proof. For example, Karl Popper once wrote that "In the empirical sciences, which alone can furnish us with information about the world we live in, proofs do not occur, if we mean by 'proof' an argument which establishes once and for ever the truth of a theory."[23] [24] Albert Einstein said:
However, in contrast to the ideal of infallible proof, in practice theories may be said to be proved according to some standard of proof used in a given inquiry.[25] [26] In this limited sense, proof is the high degree of acceptance of a theory following a process of inquiry and critical evaluation according to the standards of a scientific community.[25] [26]
Notes and References
- Book: Taper . Mark L. . Lele . Subhash . 2004 . The nature of scientific evidence: a forward-looking synthesis . Taper . Mark L. . Lele . Subhash . The nature of scientific evidence: statistical, philosophical, and empirical considerations . Chicago . . 527–551 (547) . 0226789551 . 54461920 . 10.7208/chicago/9780226789583.003.0016 . Scientific evidence is generally taken to be anything tending to refute or confirm a hypothesis..
- science-theory-observation . Theory and observation in science . Nora Mills . Boyd . James . Bogen . James Bogen . June 14, 2021. "Discussions about empirical evidence have tended to focus on epistemological questions regarding its role in theory testing ... even though empirical evidence also plays important and philosophically interesting roles in other areas including scientific discovery, the development of experimental tools and techniques, and the application of scientific theories to practical problems."
- Book: Longino, Helen. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 46. March 1979. 37–42.
- Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolution, 2nd Ed. (1970).
- http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/epistemology-bayesian/ William Talbott "Bayesian Epistemology"
- http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2007/entries/evidence/ Thomas Kelly "Evidence"
- George Kenneth Stone, "Evidence in Science"(1966)
- Karl R. Popper,"The Logic of Scientific Discovery" (1959).
- https://www.fjc.gov/sites/default/files/2012/sciman00.pdf Reference Manual on Scientific Evidence
- Mayo . Deborah G. . Deborah Mayo . September 2000 . Experimental practice and an error statistical account of evidence . . 67 . Supplement . S193–S207 . 10.1086/392819 . 188668 . 61281250 . A question regularly posed by scientists and philosophers of science is: When do empirical data provide a good test of, or reliable evidence for, a scientific hypothesis? Despite this shared interest, the considerations scientists appeal to in answering it are markedly different from those invoked in philosophical accounts of evidence and confirmation.. Mayo's paper was part of the symposium "Evidence, data generation, and scientific practice: toward a reliabilist philosophy of experiment" at the 1998 biennial meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. See also Achinstein's contribution to the symposium: Achinstein . Peter . Peter Achinstein . 2000 . Why philosophical theories of evidence are (and ought to be) ignored by scientists . . 67 . Supplement . S180–S192 . 10.1086/392818 . 188667. 120774584 .
- Book: Carnap . Rudolf . Rudolf Carnap . 1962 . 1950 . Logical foundations of probability . 2nd . Chicago . . 462 . 978-0226093437 . 372957 . registration.
- Book: Achinstein . Peter . Peter Achinstein . 1983 . The concept of evidence . Oxford readings in philosophy . Oxford; New York . . 0198750625 . registration.
- Bechtel . William . William Bechtel . 1990 . Scientific evidence: creating and evaluating experimental instruments and research techniques . PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association . 1990 . 1 . 559–572 (561) . 192732 . 10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1990.1.192732. 62119768 .
- McArthur . Dan . August 2003 . Book review: Peter Achinstein, The book of evidence . . 23 . 4 . 235–237 . Achinstein's four concepts are also summarized in: Book: Achinstein . Peter . Peter Achinstein . 2014 . 2008 . Evidence . Curd . Martin . Psillos . Stathis . Stathis Psillos . The Routledge companion to philosophy of science . 2nd . Routledge philosophy companions . London; New York . . 381–392 . 9780415518741 . 824535995 . 10.4324/9780203744857.
- simplicity . Simplicity . Alan . Baker . 20 December 2016.
- Vitányi . Paul M. B. . Paul Vitányi . Li . Ming . Ming Li . March 2000 . Minimum description length induction, Bayesianism, and Kolmogorov complexity . . 46 . 2 . 446–464 . 10.1109/18.825807 . cs/9901014 . 5971084 . See also Chapter 5 in: Book: Li . Ming . Vitányi . Paul . 2019 . An introduction to Kolmogorov complexity and its applications . 4th . Texts in computer science . Cham . . 978-3030112974 . 1106165074 . 10.1007/978-3-030-11298-1. 184483493 .
- simplici . Simplicity in the philosophy of science . Simon . Fitzpatrick . 2013. See especially Sections 1b and 4c.
- For example: Book: Schindler, Samuel . 2018 . Testability and non–ad hocness . Theoretical virtues in science: uncovering reality through theory . Cambridge, UK; New York . . 6–7 . 978-1108422260 . 10.1017/9781108381352 . No other criterion of a good scientific theory is as widely recognized as the falsifiability or testability of a theory—not only within the philosophy of science, but also way beyond it.. And: Web site: Understanding Science 101: Testing scientific ideas . undsci.berkeley.edu . 14 April 2022 . . Testing hypotheses and theories is at the core of the process of science..
- Book: Thagard . Paul . Paul Thagard . Toombs . Ethan . 2005 . Atoms, categorization and conceptual change . Cohen . Henri . Lefebvre . Claire . Handbook of categorization in cognitive science . Amsterdam . . 243–254 (253) . 0080446124 . 60667797 . 10.1016/B978-008044612-7/50065-2 . http://cogsci.uwaterloo.ca/Articles/atoms.pdf . The features of abductive prototypes are hypothesized in order to explain observations, as when Rutherford inferred that the mass of an atom is concentrated in a very small region in order to explain why alpha particles pass through gold foil. Abductive prototypes can change dramatically when new data require revision of hypotheses concerning explanatory features. This is just what happened to the concept of an atom when the experiments of Thompson and Rutherford revealed the divisibility of atoms.. Rutherford's interpretation of the Geiger–Marsden experiment is also mentioned as an example of abduction in: Book: Faye . Jan . Jan Faye . 2014 . On interpretation . The nature of scientific thinking: on interpretation, explanation, and understanding . Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire; New York . . 60–84 . 978-1137389824 . 870285649 . 10.1057/9781137389831_3.
- Campbell, Donald T. (1984) "Foreword". In Book: Yin, Robert K. . Robert K. Yin . 2018 . 1984 . Case study research: design and methods . 6th . Los Angeles . . xiii–xiv . 978-1506336169 . 983826254 . More and more I have come to the conclusion that the core of the scientific method is not experimentation per se but rather the strategy connoted by the phrase 'plausible rival hypotheses'. This strategy may start its puzzle solving with evidence, or it may start with hypothesis. Rather than presenting this hypothesis or evidence in the context-independent manner of positivistic confirmation (or even of postpositivistic corroboration), it is presented instead in extended networks of implications that (although never complete) are nonetheless crucial to its scientific evaluation. This strategy includes making explicit other implications of the hypothesis for other available data and reporting how these fit. It also includes seeking out rival explanations of the focal evidence and examining their plausibility. The plausibility of these rivals is usually reduced by ramification extinction, that is, by looking at their other implications on other data sets and seeing how well these fit.. This idea is further discussed in several chapters in: Book: Bickman . Leonard . 2000 . Donald Campbell's legacy . Thousand Oaks, CA . . 42603382.
- For example: Web site: Thematic issue: Scientific method as a problem-solving and question-answering technique: Vol. 47, No. 1 of Synthese . April 1981 . One article from the issue is: Nickles . Thomas . April 1981 . What is a problem that we may solve it? . . 47 . 1 . 85–118 . 20115620 . 10.1007/BF01064267 . 46982553 . Data sometimes do not constitute the problem (or the primary problem) but serve chiefly as evidence that a problem (or at least a deeper problem) exists.. See also: Book: Nickles, Thomas . 1988 . Questioning and problems in philosophy of science: problem-solving versus directly truth-seeking epistemologies . Meyer . Michel . Questions and questioning . Grundlagen der Kommunikation = Foundations of communication . Berlin; New York . . 43–67 . 3110106809 . 10.1515/9783110864205.43. And from a scientist's perspective: Web site: Krauss . Lawrence M. . Lawrence Krauss . 14 May 2015 . The big unanswered questions . . 15 May 2015.
- See, for example, Web site: Greenpeace co-founder: No scientific proof humans are dominant cause of warming climate . . 28 February 2014 . 19 March 2014.
- Book: Popper, Karl . 2011 . 1966 . . 5th . Routledge . 229–230 . 978-1136700323 . Karl Popper .
- Web site: 29+ Evidences for Macroevolution . . 1999–2012 . 19 March 2014 . Theobald, Douglas.
- Walton . Douglas N. . Douglas N. Walton . Zhang . Nanning . May 2013 . The epistemology of scientific evidence . Artificial Intelligence and Law . 21 . 2 . 173–219 (214) . 10.1007/s10506-012-9132-9 . Traditional epistemology established knowledge on the basis of a false concept—true belief. On our theory, scientific evidence should be based on a process of justifying the agent's reasonable acceptance of a hypothesis in an inquiry that ends in proof. We have shown in section V how this procedure can be modeled using the Carneades Argumentation System. Any proposition that cannot be proved in an inquiry to an appropriate standard of proof following this kind of epistemological procedure is not acceptable as knowledge..
- Book: Walton, Douglas N. . Douglas N. Walton . 2016 . Argument evaluation and evidence . Law, governance and technology series . 23 . Cham; New York . . 224 . 9783319196268 . 919080389 . 10.1007/978-3-319-19626-8 . To say that something is knowledge, it is important that the proposition claimed as knowledge be based on evidence of a kind that reaches a level where the proposition passes beyond the level of being accepted as true because it is based on evidence. Only when it is proved by a certain kind of evidence, that is sufficient for the discipline, or more generally the context in which the proposition was claimed, can something be properly said to be knowledge. The standard has to be high enough in a scientific inquiry to minimize the possibility that the proposition accepted as true will later have to be retracted..