Reduction (computability theory) explained
In computability theory, many reducibility relations (also called reductions, reducibilities, and notions of reducibility) are studied. They are motivated by the question: given sets
and
of natural numbers, is it possible to effectively convert a method for deciding membership in
into a method for deciding membership in
? If the answer to this question is affirmative then
is said to be
reducible to
.
The study of reducibility notions is motivated by the study of decision problems. For many notions of reducibility, if any noncomputable set is reducible to a set
then
must also be noncomputable. This gives a powerful technique for proving that many sets are noncomputable.
Reducibility relations
A reducibility relation is a binary relation on sets of natural numbers that is
is reducible to a set
and
is reducible to a set
then
is reducible to
.These two properties imply that reducibility is a
preorder on the powerset of the natural numbers. Not all preorders are studied as reducibility notions, however. The notions studied in computability theory have the informal property that
is reducible to
if and only if any (possibly noneffective) decision procedure for
can be effectively converted to a decision procedure for
. The different reducibility relations vary in the methods they permit such a conversion process to use.
Degrees of a reducibility relation
Every reducibility relation (in fact, every preorder) induces an equivalence relation on the powerset of the natural numbers in which two sets are equivalent if and only if each one is reducible to the other. In computability theory, these equivalence classes are called the degrees of the reducibility relation. For example, the Turing degrees are the equivalence classes of sets of naturals induced by Turing reducibility.
The degrees of any reducibility relation are partially ordered by the relation in the following manner. Let
be a reducibility relation and let
and
be two of its degrees. Then
if and only if there is a set
in
and a set
in
such that
. This is equivalent to the property that for every set
in
and every set
in
,
, because any two sets in
C are equivalent and any two sets in
are equivalent. It is common, as shown here, to use boldface notation to denote degrees.
Turing reducibility
See main article: Turing reduction.
The most fundamental reducibility notion is Turing reducibility. A set
of natural numbers is
Turing reducible to a set
if and only if there is an
oracle Turing machine that, when run with
as its oracle set, will compute the
indicator function (characteristic function) of
. Equivalently,
is Turing reducible to
if and only if there is an algorithm for computing the indicator function for
provided that the algorithm is provided with a means to correctly answer questions of the form "Is
in
?".
Turing reducibility serves as a dividing line for other reducibility notions because, according to the Church-Turing thesis, it is the most general reducibility relation that is effective. Reducibility relations that imply Turing reducibility have come to be known as strong reducibilities, while those that are implied by Turing reducibility are weak reducibilities. Equivalently, a strong reducibility relation is one whose degrees form a finer equivalence relation than the Turing degrees, while a weak reducibility relation is one whose degrees form a coarser equivalence relation than Turing equivalence.
Reductions stronger than Turing reducibility
The strong reducibilities include
is one-one reducible to
if there is a computable
one-to-one function
with
for all
.
is many-one reducible to
if there is a computable function
with
for all
.
is truth-table reducible to
if
is Turing reducible to
via a single (oracle) Turing machine which produces a total function relative to every oracle.
is weak truth-table reducible to
if there is a Turing reduction from
to
and a computable function
which bounds the use. Whenever
is truth-table reducible to
,
is also weak truth-table reducible to
, since one can construct a computable bound on the use by considering the maximum use over the tree of all oracles, which will exist if the reduction is total on all oracles.
is positive reducible to
if and only if
is truth-table reducible to
in a way that one can compute for every
a formula consisting of atoms of the form
such that these atoms are combined by and's and or's, where the and of
and
is 1 if
and
and so on.
Similar to positive reducibility, relating to the effective procedure of enumerability from
to
.- Disjunctive reducible: Similar to positive reducible with the additional constraint that only or's are permitted.
- Conjunctive reducibility: Similar to positive reducibility with the additional constraint that only and's are permitted.
- Linear reducibility: Similar to positive reducibility but with the constraint that all atoms of the form
are combined by
exclusive or's. In other words,
is linear reducible to
if and only if a computable function computes for each
a finite set
given as an explicit list of numbers such that
if and only if
contains an odd number of elements of
.Many of these were introduced by Post (1944). Post was searching for a non-
computable,
computably enumerable set which the
halting problem could not be Turing reduced to. As he could not construct such a set in 1944, he instead worked on the analogous problems for the various reducibilities that he introduced. These reducibilities have since been the subject of much research, and many relationships between them are known.
Bounded reducibilities
A bounded form of each of the above strong reducibilities can be defined. The most famous of these is bounded truth-table reduction, but there are also bounded Turing, bounded weak truth-table, and others. These first three are the most common ones and they are based on the number of queries. For example, a set
is bounded truth-table reducible to
if and only if the Turing machine
computing
relative to
computes a list of up to
numbers, queries
on these numbers and then terminates for all possible oracle answers; the value
is a constant independent of
. The difference between bounded weak truth-table and bounded Turing reduction is that in the first case, the up to
queries have to be made at the same time while in the second case, the queries can be made one after the other. For that reason, there are cases where
is bounded Turing reducible to
but not weak truth-table reducible to
.
Strong reductions in computational complexity
See main article: Reduction (complexity).
The strong reductions listed above restrict the manner in which oracle information can be accessed by a decision procedure but do not otherwise limit the computational resources available. Thus if a set
is
decidable then
is reducible to any set
under any of the strong reducibility relations listed above, even if
is not polynomial-time or exponential-time decidable. This is acceptable in the study of computability theory, which is interested in theoretical computability, but it is not reasonable for
computational complexity theory, which studies which sets can be decided under certain asymptotical resource bounds.
The most common reducibility in computational complexity theory is polynomial-time reducibility; a set A is polynomial-time reducible to a set
if there is a polynomial-time function
f such that for every
,
is in
if and only if
is in
. This reducibility is, essentially, a resource-bounded version of many-one reducibility. Other resource-bounded reducibilities are used in other contexts of computational complexity theory where other resource bounds are of interest.
Reductions weaker than Turing reducibility
Although Turing reducibility is the most general reducibility that is effective, weaker reducibility relations are commonly studied. These reducibilities are related to the relative definability of sets over arithmetic or set theory. They include:
is arithmetical in a set
if
is definable over the standard model of Peano arithmetic with an extra predicate for
. Equivalently, according to
Post's theorem,
A is arithmetical in
if and only if
is Turing reducible to
, the
th
Turing jump of
, for some natural number
. The
arithmetical hierarchy gives a finer classification of arithmetical reducibility.
- Hyperarithmetical reducibility: A set
is hyperarithmetical in a set
if
is
definable (see
analytical hierarchy) over the standard model of Peano arithmetic with a predicate for
. Equivalently,
is hyperarithmetical in
if and only if
is Turing reducible to
, the
th
Turing jump of
, for some
-
recursive ordinal
.
- Relative constructibility
A set
is relatively constructible from a set
if
is in
, the smallest transitive model of
ZFC set theory containing
and all the ordinals.
References
- K. Ambos-Spies and P. Fejer, 2006. "Degrees of Unsolvability." Unpublished preprint.
- P. Odifreddi, 1989. Classical Recursion Theory, North-Holland.
- P. Odifreddi, 1999. Classical Recursion Theory, Volume II, Elsevier.
- E. Post, 1944, "Recursively enumerable sets of positive integers and their decision problems", Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, volume 50, pages 284 - 316.
- H. Rogers, Jr., 1967. The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability, second edition 1987, MIT Press. (paperback),
- G. Sacks, 1990. Higher Recursion Theory, Springer-Verlag.
External links