Quietism (philosophy) explained

Quietism in philosophy sees the role of philosophy as broadly therapeutic or remedial.[1] Quietist philosophers believe that philosophy has no positive thesis to contribute; rather, it defuses confusions in the linguistic and conceptual frameworks of other subjects, including non-quietist philosophy.[2] For quietists, advancing knowledge or settling debates (particularly those between realists and non-realists) is not the job of philosophy, rather philosophy should liberate the mind by diagnosing confusing concepts.[3]

Status within philosophy

Crispin Wright said that "Quietism is the view that significant metaphysical debate is impossible."[4] [5] It has been described as "the view or stance that entails avoidance of substantive philosophical theorizing and is usually associated with certain forms of skepticism, pragmatism, and minimalism about truth. More particularly, it is opposed to putting forth positive theses and developing constructive arguments."[6]

Quietism by its nature is not a philosophical school as understood in the sense of a systematic body of truths. The objective of quietism is to show that philosophical positions or theories cannot solve problems, settle debates or advance knowledge.[7] [8]

It is often raised in discussion as an opposite position to both philosophical realism and anti-realism.[9] [10] Specifically, quietists deny that there is any substantial debate between the positions of realism and non-realism. There are a range of justifications for quietism about the realism debate offered by Gideon Rosen and John McDowell.

History and proponents

Ancient

Pyrrhonism represents perhaps the earliest example of an identifiably quietist position in the West.[11] The Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus described Pyrrhonism as a form of philosophical therapy:

Some have identified Epicureans as another early proponent of quietism.[12] [13] The goal of Epicurean philosophy is the decidedly quietist objectives of aponia (freedom from pain) and ataraxia, even dismissing Stoic logic as useless.

The neo-Confucian philosopher Cheng Hao is also associated with advocating quietism.[14] He argued that the goal of existence should be calming one's natural biases and embracing impartial tranquility. This aversion to bias is nevertheless quite distinct from Wittgenstein's position.

Contemporary

Contemporary discussion of quietism can be traced back to Ludwig Wittgenstein, whose work greatly influenced the ordinary language philosophers. While Wittgenstein himself did not advocate quietism, he expressed sympathy with the viewpoint.[15] One of the early 'ordinary language' works, Gilbert Ryle's The Concept of Mind, attempted to demonstrate that dualism arises from a failure to appreciate that mental vocabulary and physical vocabulary are simply different ways of describing one and the same thing, namely human behaviour. J. L. Austin's Sense and Sensibilia took a similar approach to the problems of skepticism and the reliability of sense perception, arguing that they arise only by misconstruing ordinary language, not because there is anything genuinely wrong with empirical evidence. Norman Malcolm, a friend of Wittgenstein's, took a quietist approach to skeptical problems in the philosophy of mind.

More recently, the philosophers John McDowell, Irad Kimhi, Sabina Lovibond, Eric Marcus, Gideon Rosen, and to a certain degree Richard Rorty[16] have taken explicitly quietist positions. Pete Mandik has argued for a position of qualia quietism on the hard problem of consciousness.[17]

Varieties

Some philosophers have advanced quietism about specific subjects such as realism or truth.[18] These positions can be held independent of one's view on quietism about the entire project of philosophy.

On realism

One may be a realist about a range of subjects within philosophy from ethics and aesthetics to science and mathematics. Realists claim that a given concept exists, has particular properties and is in some way mind independent, while non-realists deny this claim. Quietists take a third position, claiming that there is no real debate between realists and non-realists on a given subject. A version of this position espoused by John McDowell claims that the debate hinges on theses about the relationship between the mind and the world around us that are unsupported or unsupportable, and without those claims there will be no debate. Others, such as Gideon Rosen argue more specifically against individual cases of the realism debate.

On truth

Quietism about truth is a version of the identity theory of truth. Specifically, Jennifer Hornsby and John McDowell argue against any ontological gap between what we think is true and what is actually true.[19] Quietists about truth resist the distinction between truth bearers and truthmakers as leading to a correspondence theory of truth. Rather they claim that such a distinction should be eliminated, true statements are simply one thinking truly about the world. The target of these thoughts is not a truthbearer, but rather the facts of the world themselves.

See also

Sources

Notes and References

  1. Book: Bakhurst, David. The Oxford companion to philosophy. 2005. Oxford University Press. Ted Honderich. 2005. 978-0-19-153265-8. 2nd. [Oxford]. 779. 62563098. quietism, philosophical...Philosophy's proper role is therapeutic, rather than constructive: the philosopher diagnoses conceptual confusions..
  2. Virvidakis. Stelios. Kindi. Vasso. Quietism. Oxford Bibliographies Online Datasets. 2013. 10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0184.
  3. Book: Bakhurst, David. The Oxford companion to philosophy. 2005. Oxford University Press. Ted Honderich. 2005. 978-0-19-153265-8. 2nd. [Oxford]. 779. 62563098. philosophy should not aspire to produce substantive theories (e.g. of the nature of meaning, the foundations of knowledge, or of the mind's place in the world), adjudicate disputes in science or mathematics, make discoveries...Philosophy's proper role is therapeutic, rather than constructive: the philosopher diagnoses conceptual confusions. Although the results of such therapy can be profoundly liberating, philosophy does not itself advance human knowledge..
  4. Book: Wright, Crispin . Truth and Objectivity . Harvard University Press . 1994 . 9780674910874 . Cambridge, Mass. . 202.
  5. See also "Philosophers who subscribe to quietism deny that there can be such a thing as substantial metaphysical debate between realists and their non-realist opponents (because they either deny that there are substantial questions about existence or deny that there are substantial questions about independence)." https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/realism/
  6. Web site: Quietism.
  7. Book: Bakhurst, David. The Oxford companion to philosophy. 2005. Oxford University Press. Ted Honderich. 2005. 978-0-19-153265-8. 2nd. [Oxford]. 779. 62563098. philosophy should not aspire to produce substantive theories (e.g. the nature of meaning, the foundations of knowledge, or of the mind's place in the world...philosophy does not itself advance human knowledge, but 'leaves everything as it is'..
  8. Book: Blackburn, Simon. The Oxford dictionary of philosophy. 2016. 2016. 978-0-19-179955-6. 3rd. Oxford. 398. 945776618. there is no standpoint from which to achieve the philosophical goal of a theory about some concept or another..
  9. Web site: Quietism.
  10. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/realism/. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Realism. 2019. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  11. Web site: Virvidakis. Stelios. Kindi. Vasso. Quietism. 2021-04-10. Oxford Bibliographies. en. The first conception of philosophical quietism in the history of Western thought is encountered in the approach of Pyrrhonian skeptics of the Hellenistic period, who pursued imperturbability, quietude or tranquility of mind (ataraxia) through suspension of judgment (epoché) and refused assent (synkatathesis) to any philosophical thesis..
  12. Book: Encyclopedia of philosophy. 2006. Thomson Gale/Macmillan Reference USA. Donald M. Borchert. 0-02-865780-2. 2nd. 10. Detroit. 61151356.
  13. Book: Inwood. Brad. Encyclopedia of philosophy. Jones. Alexander. 2006. Thomson Gale/Macmillan Reference USA. Donald M. Borchert. 0-02-865780-2. 2nd. 4. Detroit. 300–303. 61151356. while Epicurus rejected logic along with many other specialized intellectual endeavors as useless. For Epicurus even physics mattered only in so far as it was essential to achieving tranquility..
  14. Book: Chan, Wing-tsit. Encyclopedia of philosophy. 2006. Thomson Gale/Macmillan Reference USA. Donald M. Borchert. 2006. 0-02-865780-2. 2nd. Detroit. 144–145. 61151356. The chief task of moral and spiritual cultivation is to calm one's nature through absolute impartiality...Under the influence of Buddhism Cheng Hao also advocated quietism..
  15. Book: Blackburn, Simon. The Oxford dictionary of philosophy. 2016. 978-0-19-179955-6. 3rd. Oxford. 398. 945776618. In philosophy the doctrine doubtfully associated with Wittgenstein...Wittgenstein sympathized with this but his own practice include a relentless striving to gain a 'perspicacious representation' of perplexing elements in our thought.
  16. Kraugerud. Hanne Andrea. Ramberg. Bjørn Torgrim. 2010. The New Loud: Richard Rorty, Quietist?. Common Knowledge. 16. 1. 48–65. 10.1215/0961754X-2009-060. 1538-4578.
  17. Mandik. Pete. 2016. Meta-Illusionism and Qualia Quietism. Journal of Consciousness Studies. 23. 11–12.
  18. Candlish. Stewart. Damnjanovic. Nic. 1996-03-28. The Identity Theory of Truth. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. en. Quietism Jennifer Hornsby (1997, 1999) and McDowell (on an alternative reading to that of Fish and Macdonald) endorse a version of the identity theory they see as truistic and which they put forward as an antidote to substantive theorizing about truth..
  19. Candlish. Stewart. Damnjanovic. Nic. 1996-03-28. The Identity Theory of Truth. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. en. While Hornsby and McDowell characterize the resulting view as an identity conception of truth, it is important to realize that they resist inflating the above remarks into an identification of truth bearers and truthmakers. To do so, they appear to think, is to move us beyond the truisms in a way which pushes us towards a correspondence theory of truth. The alternative appears to be to abandon the distinction between truth bearers and truthmakers entirely..