Quasitransitive relation explained

The mathematical notion of quasitransitivity is a weakened version of transitivity that is used in social choice theory and microeconomics. Informally, a relation is quasitransitive if it is symmetric for some values and transitive elsewhere. The concept was introduced by to study the consequences of Arrow's theorem.

Formal definition

A binary relation T over a set X is quasitransitive if for all a, b, and c in X the following holds:

(a\operatorname{T}b)\wedge\neg(b\operatorname{T}a)\wedge(b\operatorname{T}c)\wedge\neg(c\operatorname{T}b)(a\operatorname{T}c)\wedge\neg(c\operatorname{T}a).

If the relation is also antisymmetric, T is transitive.

Alternately, for a relation T, define the asymmetric or "strict" part P:

(a\operatorname{P}b)\Leftrightarrow(a\operatorname{T}b)\wedge\neg(b\operatorname{T}a).

Then T is quasitransitive if and only if P is transitive.

Examples

Preferences are assumed to be quasitransitive (rather than transitive) in some economic contexts. The classic example is a person indifferent between 7 and 8 grams of sugar and indifferent between 8 and 9 grams of sugar, but who prefers 9 grams of sugar to 7.[1] Similarly, the Sorites paradox can be resolved by weakening assumed transitivity of certain relations to quasitransitivity.

Properties

See also

References

Notes and References

  1. Semiorders and a Theory of Utility Discrimination . Robert Duncan Luce . Robert Duncan Luce . Econometrica . 24 . 2 . 178–191 . Apr 1956 . 10.2307/1905751. 1905751 . Here: p.179; Luce's original example consists in 400 comparisons (of coffee cups with different amounts of sugar) rather than just 2.
  2. The naminig follows, p.2-3. - For the only-if part, define xJy as xRyyRx, and define xPy as xRy ∧ ¬yRx. - For the if part, assume xRy ∧ ¬yRxyRz ∧ ¬zRy holds. Then xPy and yPz, since xJy or yJz would contradict ¬yRx or ¬zRy. Hence xPz by transitivity, ¬xJz by disjointness, ¬zJx by symmetry. Therefore, zRx would imply zPx, and, by transitivity, zPy, which contradicts ¬zRy. Altogether, this proves xRz ∧ ¬zRx.
  3. For example, if R is an equivalence relation, J may be chosen as the empty relation, or as R itself, and P as its complement.
  4. Given R, whenever xRy ∧ ¬yRx holds, the pair (x,y) can't belong to the symmetric part, but must belong to the transitive part.
  5. Since the empty relation is trivially both transitive and symmetric.
  6. The antisymmetry of R forces J to be coreflexive; hence the union of J and the transitive P is again transitive.