In quantum mechanics, the consistent histories or simply "consistent quantum theory"[1] interpretation generalizes the complementarity aspect of the conventional Copenhagen interpretation. The approach is sometimes called decoherent histories[2] and in other work decoherent histories are more specialized.[1]
First proposed by Robert Griffiths in 1984,[3] [4] this interpretation of quantum mechanics is based on a consistency criterion that then allows probabilities to be assigned to various alternative histories of a system such that the probabilities for each history obey the rules of classical probability while being consistent with the Schrödinger equation. In contrast to some interpretations of quantum mechanics, the framework does not include "wavefunction collapse" as a relevant description of any physical process, and emphasizes that measurement theory is not a fundamental ingredient of quantum mechanics. Consistent Histories allows predictions related to the state of the universe needed for quantum cosmology.[5]
The interpretation rests on three assumptions:
The third assumption generalizes complementarity and this assumption separates consistent histories from other quantum theory interpretations.[1]
A homogeneous history
Hi
i
Pi,j
ti,j
j
Hi=(Pi,1,Pi,2
,\ldots,P | |
i,ni |
)
and read it as "the proposition
Pi,1
ti,1
Pi,2
ti,2
\ldots
ti,1<ti,2<\ldots<
t | |
i,ni |
Inhomogeneous histories are multiple-time propositions which cannot be represented by a homogeneous history. An example is the logical OR of two homogeneous histories:
Hi\lorHj
These propositions can correspond to any set of questions that include all possibilities.Examples might be the three propositions meaning "the electron went through the left slit", "the electron went through the right slit" and "the electron didn't go through either slit". One of the aims of the approach is to show that classical questions such as, "where are my keys?" are consistent. In this case one might use a large number of propositions each one specifying the location of the keys in some small region of space.
Each single-time proposition
Pi,j
\hat{P}i,j
An important construction in the consistent histories approach is the class operator for a homogeneous history:
\hat{C} | |
Hi |
:=T
ni | |
\prod | |
j=1 |
\hat{P}i,j(ti,j)=
\hat{P} | |
i,ni |
… \hat{P}i,2\hat{P}i,1
The symbol
T
ti,j
t
t
Central to the consistent histories is the notion of consistency. A set of histories
\{Hi\}
\operatorname{Tr}(\hat{C} | |
Hi |
\rho
\dagger | |
\hat{C} | |
Hj |
)=0
for all
i ≠ j
\rho
The set of histories is weakly consistent if
\operatorname{Tr}(\hat{C} | |
Hi |
\rho
\dagger | |
\hat{C} | |
Hj |
) ≈ 0
for all
i ≠ j
If a set of histories is consistent then probabilities can be assigned to them in a consistent way. We postulate that the probability of history
Hi
\operatorname{Pr}(Hi)=
\operatorname{Tr}(\hat{C} | |
Hi |
\rho
\dagger | |
\hat{C} | |
Hi |
)
which obeys the axioms of probability if the histories
Hi
As an example, this means the probability of "
Hi
Hj
Hi
Hj
Hi
Hj
The interpretation based on consistent histories is used in combination with the insights about quantum decoherence. Quantum decoherence implies that irreversible macroscopic phenomena (hence, all classical measurements) render histories automatically consistent, which allows one to recover classical reasoning and "common sense" when applied to the outcomes of these measurements. More precise analysis of decoherence allows (in principle) a quantitative calculation of the boundary between the classical domain and the quantum domain. According to Roland Omnès,[6]
In order to obtain a complete theory, the formal rules above must be supplemented with a particular Hilbert space and rules that govern dynamics, for example a Hamiltonian.
In the opinion of others[7] this still does not make a complete theory as no predictions are possible about which set of consistent histories will actually occur. In other words, the rules of consistent histories, the Hilbert space, and the Hamiltonian must be supplemented by a set selection rule. However, Robert B. Griffiths holds the opinion that asking the question of which set of histories will "actually occur" is a misinterpretation of the theory;[8] histories are a tool for description of reality, not separate alternate realities.
Proponents of this consistent histories interpretation—such as Murray Gell-Mann, James Hartle, Roland Omnès and Robert B. Griffiths—argue that their interpretation clarifies the fundamental disadvantages of the old Copenhagen interpretation, and can be used as a complete interpretational framework for quantum mechanics.
In Quantum Philosophy,[9] Roland Omnès provides a less mathematical way of understanding this same formalism.
The consistent histories approach can be interpreted as a way of understanding which sets of classical questions can be consistently asked of a single quantum system, and which sets of questions are fundamentally inconsistent, and thus meaningless when asked together. It thus becomes possible to demonstrate formally why it is that the questions which Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen assumed could be asked together, of a single quantum system, simply cannot be asked together. On the other hand, it also becomes possible to demonstrate that classical, logical reasoning often does apply, even to quantum experiments – but we can now be mathematically exact about the limits of classical logic.