Problem of time explained

In theoretical physics, the problem of time is a conceptual conflict between general relativity and quantum mechanics in that quantum mechanics regards the flow of time as universal and absolute, whereas general relativity regards the flow of time as malleable and relative.[1] [2] This problem raises the question of what time really is in a physical sense and whether it is truly a real, distinct phenomenon. It also involves the related question of why time seems to flow in a single direction, despite the fact that no known physical laws at the microscopic level seem to require a single direction.[3]

Time in quantum mechanics

In classical mechanics, a special status is assigned to time in the sense that it is treated as a classical background parameter, external to the system itself. This special role is seen in the standard formulation of quantum mechanics. It is regarded as part of a priori given a classical background with a well-defined value. The classical treatment of time is intertwined with the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, and, thus, with the conceptual foundations of quantum theory: all measurements of observables are made at certain instants of time and probabilities are only assigned to such measurements.

Overturning of absolute time in general relativity

Though classically spacetime appears to be an absolute background, within general relativity time is no longer a background parameter, but must be considered on equal footing with space, and time and space evolve together as spacetime. Gravity is a manifestation of spacetime geometry, and spacetime is not fixed, but dynamic, as evidenced by phenomena such as gravitational waves.

Proposed solutions to the problem of time

The quantum concept of time first emerged from early research on quantum gravity, in particular from the work of Bryce DeWitt in the 1960s:,[4] which resulted in the Wheeler–DeWitt equation.

In other words, time is an entanglement phenomenon, which places all equal clock readings (of correctly prepared clocks – or any objects usable as clocks) into the same history. This was first understood by physicists Don Page and William Wootters in 1983.[5] They proposed to address the problem of time in systems like general relativity called conditional probabilities interpretation.[6] It consists in promoting all variables to quantum operators, one of them as a clock, and asking conditional probability questions with respect to other variables. They arrived at a solution based on the quantum phenomenon of entanglement. Page and Wootters showed how quantum entanglement can be used to measure time.[7]

In 2013, at the Istituto Nazionale di Ricerca Metrologica (INRIM) in Turin, Italy, Ekaterina Moreva, together with Giorgio Brida, Marco Gramegna, Vittorio Giovannetti, Lorenzo Maccone, and Marco Genovese performed the first experimental test of Page and Wootters' ideas. They confirmed for photons that time is an emergent phenomenon for internal observers but absent for external observers of the universe just as the Wheeler–DeWitt equation predicts.[8] [9] [10]

Consistent discretizations approach developed by Jorge Pullin and Rodolfo Gambini have no constraints. These are lattice approximation techniques for quantum gravity. In the canonical approach, if one discretizes the constraints and equations of motion, the resulting discrete equations are inconsistent: they cannot be solved simultaneously. To address this problem one uses a technique based on discretizing the action of the theory and working with the discrete equations of motion. These are automatically guaranteed to be consistent. Most of the hard conceptual questions of quantum gravity are related to the presence of constraints in the theory. Consistent discretized theories are free of these conceptual problems and can be straightforwardly quantized, providing a solution to the problem of time. It is a bit more subtle than this. Although without constraints and having "general evolution", the latter is only in terms of a discrete parameter that isn't physically accessible. The way out is addressed in a way similar to the Page–Wooters approach. The idea is to pick one of the physical variables to be a clock and ask relational questions. These ideas, where the clock is also quantum mechanical, have actually led to a new interpretation of quantum mechanics — the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics.[11] [12] This new interpretation solves the problems of the use of environmental decoherence as a solution to the problem of measurement in quantum mechanics by invoking fundamental limitations, due to the quantum mechanical nature of clocks, in the process of measurement. These limitations are very natural in the context of generally covariant theories as quantum gravity where the clock must be taken as one of the degrees of freedom of the system itself. They have also put forward this fundamental decoherence as a way to resolve the black hole information paradox.[13] [14] In certain circumstances, a matter field is used to de-parametrize the theory and introduce a physical Hamiltonian. This generates physical time evolution, not a constraint.

Reduced phase space quantization constraints are solved first and then quantized. This approach was considered for some time to be impossible as it seems to require first finding the general solution to Einstein's equations. However, with the use of ideas involved in Dittrich's approximation scheme (built on ideas of Carlo Rovelli) a way to explicitly implement, at least in principle, a reduced phase space quantization was made viable.[15]

Avshalom Elitzur and Shahar Dolev argue that quantum mechanical experiments such as the Quantum Liar[16] provide evidence of inconsistent histories, and that spacetime itself may therefore be subject to change affecting entire histories.[17] Elitzur and Dolev also believe that an objective passage of time and relativity can be reconciled and that it would resolve many of the issues with the block universe and the conflict between relativity and quantum mechanics.[18]

One solution to the problem of time proposed by Lee Smolin is that there exists a "thick present" of events, in which two events in the present can be causally related to each other, but in contrast to the block universe view of time in which all time exists eternally.[19] Marina Cortês and Lee Smolin argue that certain classes of discrete dynamical systems demonstrate time asymmetry and irreversibility, which is consistent with an objective passage of time.[20]

Weyl time in scale-invariant quantum gravity

Motivated by the Immirzi ambiguity in loop quantum gravity and the near conformal invariance of the standard model of elementary particles,[21] Charles Wang and co-workers have argued that the problem of time may be related to an underlying scale invariance of gravity-matter systems.[22] [23] [24] Scale invariance has also been proposed to resolve the hierarchy problem of fundamental couplings.[25] As a global continuous symmetry, scale invariance generates a conversed Weyl current according to Noether’s theorem. In scale-invariant cosmological models, this Weyl current naturally gives rise to a harmonic time.[26] In the context of loop quantum gravity, Charles Wang et al. suggest that scale invariance may lead to the existence of a quantized time.

Thermal time hypothesis

The thermal time hypothesis is a possible solution to the problem of time in classical and quantum theory as has been put forward by Carlo Rovelli and Alain Connes. Physical time flow is modeled as a fundamental property of the theory, a macroscopic feature of thermodynamical origin.[27] [28]

See also

Further reading

Notes and References

  1. http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9210011
  2. Quantum Gravity's Time Problem . Wolchover, Natalie . December 1, 2016 . Quanta Magazine .
  3. Newsflash: Time May Not Exist . Folger, Tim . June 12, 2007 . Discover .
  4. Book: Deutsch . The Fabric of Reality . 14 April 2011 . Penguin Books Limited . 978-0-14-196961-9 . 240.
  5. Book: Deutsch, David. The Beginning of Infinity: Explanations that Transform The World. 299. 2011. Penguin UK. 9780141969695.
  6. Page. Don N.. Wootters. William K.. 15 June 1983. Phys. Rev. D. 27. 2885. Evolution without evolution: Dynamics described by stationary observables. 12. 10.1103/PhysRevD.27.2885. 1983PhRvD..27.2885P.
  7. Web site: Aron. Jacob. Entangled toy universe shows time may be an illusion. https://web.archive.org/web/20161018065554/http://www.newscientist.com//article/dn24473-entangled-toy-universe-shows-time-may-be-an-illusion. 2016-10-18. October 25, 2013.
  8. Web site: Quantum Experiment Shows How Time 'Emerges' from Entanglement. The Physics arXiv Blog. Oct 23, 2013. https://web.archive.org/web/20170603063357/https://medium.com/the-physics-arxiv-blog/quantum-experiment-shows-how-time-emerges-from-entanglement-d5d3dc850933. 2017-06-03.
  9. Moreva. Ekaterina. Brida. Giorgio. Gramegna. Marco. Giovannetti. Vittorio. Maccone. Lorenzo. Genovese. Marco. Time from quantum entanglement: An experimental illustration. Physical Review A. 20 May 2014. 89. 5. 052122. 10.1103/PhysRevA.89.052122. 1310.4691. 2014PhRvA..89e2122M. 118638346 .
  10. Moreva. Ekaterina. Gramegna. Marco. Brida. Giorgio. Maccone. Lorenzo. Genovese. Marco. Quantum time: Experimental multitime correlations. Physical Review D. 16 November 2017. 96 . 5. 102005. 10.1103/PhysRevD.96.102005. 1710.00707. 2017PhRvD..96j2005M. 119431509 .
  11. Gambini. Rodolfo. Pullin. Jorge. The Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics: frequently asked questions. Journal of Physics: Conference Series. 1 June 2009. 174. 1. 012003. 10.1088/1742-6596/174/1/012003. 0905.4402. 2009JPhCS.174a2003G. 250680865 .
  12. Gambini. Rodolfo. Garc?a-Pintos. Luis Pedro. Pullin. Jorge. An axiomatic formulation of the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. November 2011. 42. 4. 256–263. 10.1016/j.shpsb.2011.10.002. 1002.4209. 2011SHPMP..42..256G. 993508 .
  13. Gambini. Rodolfo. Porto. Rafael A.. Pullin. Jorge. No Black Hole Information Puzzle In A Relational Universe. International Journal of Modern Physics D. December 2004. 13. 10. 2315–2320. 10.1142/S0218271804006383. hep-th/0405183. 2004IJMPD..13.2315G. 119424485 .
  14. Gambini. Rodolfo. Porto. Rafael A.. Pullin. Jorge. Realistic Clocks, Universal Decoherence, and the Black Hole Information Paradox. Physical Review Letters. 6 December 2004. 93. 24. 240401. 10.1103/PhysRevLett.93.240401. 15697783. hep-th/0406260. 2004PhRvL..93x0401G. 25174047 .
  15. Thiemann. T. Reduced phase space quantization and Dirac observables. Classical and Quantum Gravity. 21 February 2006. 23. 4. 1163–1180. 10.1088/0264-9381/23/4/006. gr-qc/0411031. 2006CQGra..23.1163T. 17230218.
  16. Elitzur, A. C., & Dolev, S. (2005). "Quantum phenomena within a new theory of time". In Quo vadis quantum mechanics? (pp. 325-349). Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg.
  17. Elitzur, A. C., & Dolev, S. (2003). "Is there more to T?. In The Nature of Time: Geometry, Physics and Perception (pp. 297-306). Springer, Dordrecht.
  18. Elitzur, A. C., & Dolev, S. (2005). "Becoming as a bridge between quantum mechanics and relativity". In Endophysics, Time, Quantum And The Subjective: (With CD-ROM) (pp. 589-606).
  19. Smolin . L . 2015 . Temporal naturalism . 1805.12468 . Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics . 52 . 86–102 . 10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.03.005 . 2015SHPMP..52...86S . 8344858 .
  20. Cortês . M. . Smolin . L. . 2018 . Reversing the irreversible: from limit cycles to emergent time symmetry . 1703.09696 . Physical Review D . 97 . 2. 026004 . 10.1103/physrevd.97.026004 . 2018PhRvD..97b6004C . 119067096 .
  21. 2007-05-10. Conformal symmetry and the Standard Model. Physics Letters B. en. 648. 4. 312–317. 10.1016/j.physletb.2007.03.023. hep-th/0612165. 0370-2693. free. Meissner. Krzysztof A.. Nicolai. Hermann. 2007PhLB..648..312M .
  22. Wang. Charles H.-T.. Stankiewicz. Marcin. 2020-01-10. Quantization of time and the big bang via scale-invariant loop gravity. Physics Letters B. en. 800. 135106. 10.1016/j.physletb.2019.135106. 1910.03300. 2020PhLB..80035106W . 0370-2693. free.
  23. Wang. Charles H.-T.. Rodrigues. Daniel P. F.. 2018-12-28. Closing the gaps in quantum space and time: Conformally augmented gauge structure of gravitation. Physical Review D. 98. 12. 124041. 10.1103/PhysRevD.98.124041. 1810.01232 . 2018PhRvD..98l4041W . 2164/11713. 118961037 . free.
  24. Wang. Charles H.-T.. 2005-10-06. Unambiguous spin-gauge formulation of canonical general relativity with conformorphism invariance. Physical Review D. 72. 8. 087501. 10.1103/PhysRevD.72.087501. gr-qc/0507044. 2005PhRvD..72h7501W . 34995566 .
  25. Shaposhnikov. Mikhail. Shkerin. Andrey. 2018-10-03. Gravity, scale invariance and the hierarchy problem. Journal of High Energy Physics. en. 2018. 10. 24. 10.1007/JHEP10(2018)024. 1029-8479. free. 1804.06376. 2018JHEP...10..024S .
  26. Ferreira. Pedro G.. Hill. Christopher T.. Ross. Graham G.. 2017-02-08. Weyl current, scale-invariant inflation, and Planck scale generation. Physical Review D. 95. 4. 043507. 10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043507. free. 1610.09243. 2017PhRvD..95d3507F .
  27. Rovelli . C . Statistical mechanics of gravity and the thermodynamical origin of time . Classical and Quantum Gravity . IOP Publishing . 10 . 1993 . 8 . 10.1088/0264-9381/10/8/015 . 1549–1566. 1993CQGra..10.1549R .
  28. Connes . A . Rovelli . C . Von Neumann algebra automorphisms and time-thermodynamics relation in generally covariant quantum theories . Classical and Quantum Gravity . IOP Publishing . 11 . 12 . 1994-12-01 . 0264-9381 . 10.1088/0264-9381/11/12/007 . 2899–2917. gr-qc/9406019. 1994CQGra..11.2899C .