Utility representation theorem explained

In economics, a utility representation theorem asserts that, under certain conditions, a preference ordering can be represented by a real-valued utility function, such that option A is preferred to option B if and only if the utility of A is larger than that of B.

Background

Suppose a person is asked questions of the form "Do you prefer A or B?" (when A and B can be options, actions to take, states of the world, consumption bundles, etc.). If the agent prefers A to B, we write

A\succB

. The set of all such preference-pairs forms the person's preference relation.

Instead of recording the person's preferences between every pair of options, it would be much more convenient to have a single utility function - a function u that assigns a real number to each option, such that

u(A)>u(B)

if and only if

A\succB

.

Not every preference-relation has a utility-function representation. For example, if the relation is not transitive (the agent prefers A to B, B to C, and C to A), then it has no utility representation, since any such utility function would have to satisfy

u(A)>u(B)>u(C)>u(A)

, which is impossible.

A utility representation theorem gives conditions on a preference relation, that are sufficient for the existence of a utility representation.

Often, one would like the representing function u to satisfy additional conditions, such as continuity. This requires additional conditions on the preference relation.

Definitions

The set of options is a topological space denoted by X. In some cases we assume that X is also a metric space; in particular, X can be a subset of a Euclidean space Rm, such that each coordinate in represents a commodity, and each m-vector in X represents a possible consumption bundle.

Preference relations

A preference relation is a subset of

X x X

. It is denoted by either

\succ

or

\succeq

:

\succ

is used when the relation is strict, that is,

A\succB

means that option A is strictly better than option B. In this case, the relation should be irreflexive, that is,

A\succA

does not hold. It should also be asymmetric, that is,

A\succB

implies that not

B\succA

.

\succeq

is used when the relation is weak, that is,

A\succeqB

means that option A is at least as good as option B (A may be equivalent to B, or better than B). In this case, the relation should be reflexive, that is,

A\succeqA

always holds. Given a weak preference relation

\succeq

, one can define its "strict part"

\succ

and "indifference part"

\simeq

as follows:

A\succB

if and only if

A\succeqB

and not

B\succeqA

.

A\simeqB

if and only if

A\succeqB

and

B\succeqA

.

Given a strict preference relation

\succ

, one can define its "weak part"

\succeq

and "indifference part"

\simeq

as follows:

A\succeqB

if and only if not

B\succA

;

A\simeqB

if and only if not

B\succA

and not

A\succB

.

For every option

A\inX

, we define the contour sets at A:

\succeq

, the weak upper contour set at A is the set of all options that are at least as good as A:

\{B\inX:B\succeqA\}

. The weak lower contour set at A is the set of all options that are at most as good as A:

\{B\inX:A\succeqB\}

.

\succ

, the strict upper contour set at A is the set of all options better than A:

\{B\inX:B\succA\}

, and the strict lower contour set at A is the set of all options worse than A:

\{B\inX:A\succB\}

.

Sometimes, the above continuity notions are called semicontinuous, and a

\succeq

is called continuous if it is a closed subset of

X x X

.[1]

A preference-relation is called:

\simeq

is countable.

Z\subseteqX

such that for every pair

A\succB

, there is an element

zi\inZ

that separates them, that is,

A\succzi\succB

(an analogous definition exists for weak relations).

As an example, the strict order ">" on real numbers is separable, but not countable.

Utility functions

A utility function is a function

u:X\toR

.

\succ

, if

u(A)>u(B)\iffA\succB

.

\succeq

, if

u(A)\gequ(B)\iffA\succeqB

.

Complete preference relations

See main article: Debreu's representation theorems. Debreu[2] [3] proved the existence of a contiuous representation of a weak preference relation

\succeq

satisfying the following conditions:
  1. Reflexive and Transitive;
  2. Complete, that is, for every two options A, B in X, either

A\succeqB

or

B\succeqA

or both;
  1. For all

A\inX

, both the upper and the lower weak contour sets are topologically closed;
  1. The space X is second-countable. This means that there is a countable set S of open sets, such that every open set in X is the union of sets of the class S.[4] Second-countability is implied by the following properties (from weaker to stronger):

\succeq

is separable.
    • The relation

\succeq

is countable.Jaffray[5] gives an elementary proof to the existence of a continuous utility function.

Incomplete preference relations

Preferences are called incomplete when some options are incomparable, that is, neither

A\succeqB

nor

B\succeqA

holds. This case is denoted by

A\bowtieB

. Since real numbers are always comparable, it is impossible to have a representing function u with

u(A)\gequ(B)\iffA\succeqB

. There are several ways to cope with this issue.

One-directional representation

Peleg[6] defined a utility function representation of a strict partial order

\succ

as a function

u:X\toR

such that

A\succB\impliesu(A)>u(B)

, that is, only one direction of implication should hold. Peleg proved the existence of a one-dimensional continuous utility representation of a strict preference relation

\succ

satisfying the following conditions:
  1. Irreflexive and transitive (which implies that it is asymmetric, that is, is a strict partial order);
  2. Separable;
  3. For all

A\inX

, the lower strict contour set at A is topologically open;
  1. Spacious: if

A\succB

, then the lower strict contour set at A contains the closure of the lower strict contour set at B.
    • This condition is required for incomplete preference relations. For complete preference relations, every relation in which all lower and upper strict contour sets are open, is also spacious.

If we are given a weak preference relation

\succeq

, we can apply Peleg's theorem by defining a strict preference relation:

A\succB

if and only if

A\succeqB

and not

B\succeqA

.

The second condition (

\succ

is separable) is implied by the following three conditions:

A\inX

, both lower and upper strict contour sets at A are topologically open;

A similar approach was taken by Richter.[7] Therefore, this one-directional representation is also called a Richter-Peleg utility representation.[8]

Jaffray[9] defines a utility function representation of a strict partial order

\succ

as a function

u:X\toR

such that both

A\succB\impliesu(A)>u(B)

, and

AB\impliesu(A)=u(B)

, where the relation

AB

is defined by: for all C,

A\succC\iffB\succC

and

C\succA\iffC\succB

(that is: the lower and upper contour sets of A and B are identical). He proved that, for every partially-ordered space

(X,\succ)

that is perfectly-separable, there exists a utility function that is upper-semicontinuous in any topology stronger than the upper order topology. An analogous statement states the existence of a utility function that is lower-semicontinuous in any topology stronger than the lower order topology.

Sondermann[10] defines a utility function representation similarly to Jaffray. He gives conditions for existence of a utility function representation on a probability space, that is upper semicontinuous or lower semicontinuous in the order topology.

Herden[11] [12] defines a utility function representation of a weak preorder

\succeq

as an isotone function

u:(X,\succeq)\to(R,\geq)

such that

A\succB\impliesu(A)>u(B)

. Herden proved that a weak preorder

\succeq

on X has a continuous utility function, if and only if there exists a countable family E of separable systems on X such that, for all pairs

A\succB

, there is a separable system F in E, such that B is contained in all sets in F, and A is not contained in any set in F. He shows that this theorem implies Peleg's representation theorem. In a follow-up paper he clarifies the relation between this theorem and classical utility representation theorems on complete orders.

Multi-utility representation

A multi-utility representation (MUR) of a relation

\succeq

is a set U of utility functions, such that

A\succeqB\iff\forallu\inU:u(A)\gequ(B)

. In other words, A is preferred to B if and only if all utility functions in the set U unanimously hold this preference. The concept was introduced by Efe Ok.[13]

Every preorder (reflexive and transitive relation) has a trivial MUR. Moreover, every preorder with closed upper contour sets has an upper-semicontinuous MUR, and every preorder with closed lower contour sets has a lower-semicontinuous MUR. However, not every preorder with closed upper and lower contour sets has a continuous MUR. Ok and Evren present several conditions on the existence of a continuous MUR:

\succeq

has a continuous MUR if-and-only-if (X,

\succeq

) is a semi-normally-preordered topological space.

\succeq

is a closed subset of

X x X

, then

\succeq

has a continuous MUR. This in particular holds if X is a nonempty closed subset of a Euclidean space.

\succeq

is a preorder with closed upper and lower contour sets, that satisfies strong local non-satiation and an additional property called niceness, then

\succeq

has a continuous MUR.

All the representations guaranteed by the above theorems might contain infinitely many utilities, and even uncountably many utilities. In practice, it is often important to have a finite MUR - a MUR with finitely many utilities. Evren and Ok prove there exists a finite MUR where all utilities are upper[lower] semicontinuous for any weak preference relation

\succeq

satisfying the following conditions:
  1. Reflexive and Transitive (that is,

\succeq

is a weak preorder);
  1. All upper[lower] contour sets are topologically closed;
  2. The space X is second-countable, that is, it has a countable basis.
  3. The width of

\succeq

(the largest size of a set in which all elements are incomparable) is finite.
    • The number of utility functions in the representation is at most the width of

\succeq

.Note that the guaranteed functions are semicontinuous, but not necessarily continuous, even if all upper and lower contour sets are closed. Evren and Ok say that "there does not seem to be a natural way of deriving a continuous finite multi-utility representation theorem, at least, not by using the methods adopted in this paper".

See also

Notes and References

  1. Evren . Özgür . Ok . Efe A. . 2011-08-01 . On the multi-utility representation of preference relations . Journal of Mathematical Economics . en . 47 . 4 . 554–563 . 10.1016/j.jmateco.2011.07.003 . 0304-4068.
  2. Book: Debreu, Gerard . Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function . 1954.
  3. Book: Debreu, Gerard . Mathematical economics : twenty papers of Gerard Debreu; introduction by Werner Hildenbrand. . 1986 . Cambridge University Press . 0-521-23736-X . 1st pbk. . Cambridge [Cambridgeshire] . 6. Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function . 25466669.
  4. Debreu, Gerard . 1964 . Continuity properties of Paretian utility . International Economic Review . 5 . 285–293 . 10.2307/2525513 . 3. 2525513 .
  5. Jaffray . Jean-Yves . 1975 . Existence of a Continuous Utility Function: An Elementary Proof . Econometrica . 43 . 5/6 . 981–983 . 10.2307/1911340 . 1911340 . 0012-9682.
  6. Peleg . Bezalel . 1970 . Utility Functions for Partially Ordered Topological Spaces . Econometrica . 38 . 1 . 93–96 . 10.2307/1909243 . 1909243 . 0012-9682.
  7. Richter . Marcel K. . 1966 . Revealed Preference Theory . Econometrica . 34 . 3 . 635–645 . 10.2307/1909773 . 1909773 . 0012-9682.
  8. Alcantud . José Carlos R. . Bosi . Gianni . Zuanon . Magalì . 2016-03-01 . Richter–Peleg multi-utility representations of preorders . Theory and Decision . en . 80 . 3 . 443–450 . 10.1007/s11238-015-9506-z . 1573-7187. 11368/2865746 . 255110550 . free .
  9. Jaffray . Jean-Yves . 1975-12-01 . Semicontinuous extension of a partial order . Journal of Mathematical Economics . en . 2 . 3 . 395–406 . 10.1016/0304-4068(75)90005-1 . 0304-4068.
  10. Sondermann . Dieter . 1980-10-01 . Utility representations for partial orders . Journal of Economic Theory . en . 23 . 2 . 183–188 . 10.1016/0022-0531(80)90004-6 . 0022-0531.
  11. Herden . G. . 1989-06-01 . On the existence of utility functions . Mathematical Social Sciences . en . 17 . 3 . 297–313 . 10.1016/0165-4896(89)90058-9 . 0165-4896.
  12. Herden . G. . 1989-10-01 . On the existence of utility functions ii . Mathematical Social Sciences . en . 18 . 2 . 107–117 . 10.1016/0165-4896(89)90041-3 . 0165-4896.
  13. Ok . Efe . 2002 . Utility Representation of an Incomplete Preference Relation . Journal of Economic Theory . 104 . 2 . 429–449 . 10.1006/jeth.2001.2814 . 0022-0531.