Partial equivalence relation explained
In mathematics, a partial equivalence relation (often abbreviated as PER, in older literature also called restricted equivalence relation[1]) is a homogeneous binary relation that is symmetric and transitive. If the relation is also reflexive, then the relation is an equivalence relation.
Definition
Formally, a relation
on a set
is a PER if it holds for all
that:
- if
, then
(symmetry)
- if
and
, then
(transitivity)
Another more intuitive definition is that
on a set
is a PER if there is some subset
of
such that
and
is an
equivalence relation on
. The two definitions are seen to be equivalent by taking
.
[2] Properties and applications
The following properties hold for a partial equivalence relation
on a set
:
is an equivalence relation on the subset
Y=\{x\inX\midxRx\}\subseteqX
.
[3] - difunctional: the relation is the set
for two
partial functions
and some indicator set
,
and
implies
and similarly for left Euclideanness
and
imply
and
, then
and
.
[4] [5] None of these properties is sufficient to imply that the relation is a PER.[6]
In non-set-theory settings
In type theory, constructive mathematics and their applications to computer science, constructing analogues of subsets is often problematic[7] —in these contexts PERs are therefore more commonly used, particularly to define setoids, sometimes called partial setoids. Forming a partial setoid from a type and a PER is analogous to forming subsets and quotients in classical set-theoretic mathematics.
The algebraic notion of congruence can also be generalized to partial equivalences, yielding the notion of subcongruence, i.e. a homomorphic relation that is symmetric and transitive, but not necessarily reflexive.[8]
Examples
, if
is not empty.
Kernels of partial functions
If
is a
partial function on a set
, then the relation
defined by
if
is defined at
,
is defined at
, and
is a partial equivalence relation, since it is clearly symmetric and transitive.
If
is undefined on some elements, then
is not an equivalence relation. It is not reflexive since if
is not defined then
- in fact, for such an
there is no
such that
. It follows immediately that the largest subset of
on which
is an equivalence relation is precisely the subset on which
is defined.
Functions respecting equivalence relations
Let X and Y be sets equipped with equivalence relations (or PERs)
. For
, define
to mean:
\forallx0 x1, x0 ≈ Xx1 ⇒ f(x0) ≈ Yg(x1)
then
means that
f induces a well-defined function of the quotients
. Thus, the PER
captures both the idea of
definedness on the quotients and of two functions inducing the same function on the quotient.
Equality of IEEE floating point values
The IEEE 754:2008 standard for floating-point numbers defines an "EQ" relation for floating point values. This predicate is symmetric and transitive, but is not reflexive because of the presence of NaN values that are not EQ to themselves.[9]
Notes and References
- Scott . Dana . Data Types as Lattices . SIAM Journal on Computing . September 1976 . 5 . 3 . 560 . 10.1137/0205037.
- Book: Mitchell . John C. . Foundations for programming languages . 1996 . MIT Press . Cambridge, Mass. . 0585037892 . 364–365.
- By construction,
is reflexive on
and therefore an equivalence relation on
.
- https://www.britannica.com/topic/formal-logic/Logical-manipulations-in-LPC#ref534730 Encyclopaedia Britannica
- This follows since if
, then
by symmetry, so
and
by transitivity. It is also a consequence of the Euclidean properties.
- For the equivalence relation, consider the set
and the relation
R=\{a,b,c\}2\cup\{(d,a)\}
.
is an equivalence relation on
but not a PER on
since it is neither symmetric (
, but not
) nor transitive (
and
, but not
). For Euclideanness, xRy on natural numbers, defined by 0 ≤ x ≤ y+1 ≤ 2, is right Euclidean, but neither symmetric (since e.g. 2R1, but not 1R2) nor transitive (since e.g. 2R1 and 1R0, but not 2R0).
- Book: https://ieeexplore.ieee.org/document/5135. 10.1109/LICS.1988.5135. The strength of the subset type in Martin-Lof's type theory. [1988] Proceedings. Third Annual Information Symposium on Logic in Computer Science. 1988. Salveson. A.. Smith. J.M.. 384–391. 0-8186-0853-6. 15822016.
- Book: Aldo Ursini . Paulo Agliano. Logic and Algebra. 1996. CRC Press. 978-0-8247-9606-8. 161–180. J. Lambek. The Butterfly and the Serpent.
- Goldberg . David . 10.1145/103162.103163 . 1 . ACM Computing Surveys . 5–48 . What Every Computer Scientist Should Know About Floating-Point Arithmetic . 23 . 1991. See page 33.