In economics, an ordinal utility function is a function representing the preferences of an agent on an ordinal scale. Ordinal utility theory claims that it is only meaningful to ask which option is better than the other, but it is meaningless to ask how much better it is or how good it is. All of the theory of consumer decision-making under conditions of certainty can be, and typically is, expressed in terms of ordinal utility.
For example, suppose George tells us that "I prefer A to B and B to C". George's preferences can be represented by a function u such that:
u(A)=9,u(B)=8,u(C)=1
But critics of cardinal utility claim the only meaningful message of this function is the order
u(A)>u(B)>u(C)
v(A)=9,v(B)=2,v(C)=1
Ordinal utility contrasts with cardinal utility theory: the latter assumes that the differences between preferences are also important. In u the difference between A and B is much smaller than between B and C, while in v the opposite is true. Hence, u and v are not cardinally equivalent.
The ordinal utility concept was first introduced by Pareto in 1906.[1]
Suppose the set of all states of the world is
X
X
\preceq
A\preceqB
The symbol
\sim
A\simB\iff(A\preceqB\landB\preceqA)
The symbol
\prec
A\precB\iff(A\preceqB\landB\not\preceqA)
A\preceqB\iffu(A)\lequ(B)
See main article: indifference curve. Instead of defining a numeric function, an agent's preference relation can be represented graphically by indifference curves. This is especially useful when there are two kinds of goods, x and y. Then, each indifference curve shows a set of points
(x,y)
(x1,y1)
(x2,y2)
(x1,y1)\sim(x2,y2)
An example indifference curve is shown below:
Each indifference curve is a set of points, each representing a combination of quantities of two goods or services, all of which combinations the consumer is equally satisfied with. The further a curve is from the origin, the greater is the level of utility.
The slope of the curve (the negative of the marginal rate of substitution of X for Y) at any point shows the rate at which the individual is willing to trade off good X against good Y maintaining the same level of utility. The curve is convex to the origin as shown assuming the consumer has a diminishing marginal rate of substitution. It can be shown that consumer analysis with indifference curves (an ordinal approach) gives the same results as that based on cardinal utility theory — i.e., consumers will consume at the point where the marginal rate of substitution between any two goods equals the ratio of the prices of those goods (the equi-marginal principle).
Revealed preference theory addresses the problem of how to observe ordinal preference relations in the real world. The challenge of revealed preference theory lies in part in determining what goods bundles were foregone, on the basis of them being less liked, when individuals are observed choosing particular bundles of goods.[2] [3]
Some conditions on
\preceq
A\preceqB
B\preceqC
A\preceqC
A,B\inX
A\preceqB
B\preceqA
A\inX
A\preceqA
When these conditions are met and the set
X
u
\prec
X
(-1,1)
When
X
A preference relation is called continuous if, whenever B is preferred to A, small deviations from B or A will not reverse the ordering between them. Formally, a preference relation on a set X is called continuous if it satisfies one of the following equivalent conditions:
A\inX
\{(A,B)|A\preceqB\}
X x X
X
(Ai,Bi)
Ai\preceqBi
Ai\toA
Bi\toB
A\preceqB
A,B\inX
A\precB
A
B
a
A
b
B
a\precb
X
If a preference relation is represented by a continuous utility function, then it is clearly continuous. By the theorems of Debreu (1954), the opposite is also true:
Every continuous complete preference relation can be represented by a continuous ordinal utility function.
Note that the lexicographic preferences are not continuous. For example,
(5,0)\prec(5,1)
x<5
(5,0)
For every utility function v, there is a unique preference relation represented by v. However, the opposite is not true: a preference relation may be represented by many different utility functions. The same preferences could be expressed as any utility function that is a monotonically increasing transformation of v. E.g., if
v(A)\equivf(v(A))
where
f:R\toR
This equivalence is succinctly described in the following way:
An ordinal utility function is unique up to increasing monotone transformation.
In contrast, a cardinal utility function is unique up to increasing affine transformation. Every affine transformation is monotone; hence, if two functions are cardinally equivalent they are also ordinally equivalent, but not vice versa.
Suppose, from now on, that the set
X
X
(x,y)
Then under certain circumstances a preference relation
\preceq
v(x,y)
Suppose the preference relation is monotonically increasing, which means that "more is always better":
x<x'\implies(x,y)\prec(x',y)
y<y'\implies(x,y')\prec(x,y')
Then, both partial derivatives, if they exist, of v are positive. In short:
If a utility function represents a monotonically increasing preference relation, then the utility function is monotonically increasing.
Suppose a person has a bundle
(x0,y0)
(x0-λ ⋅ \delta,y0+\delta)
λ ⋅ \delta
\delta
\delta\to0
λ
(x0,y0)
This definition of the MRS is based only on the ordinal preference relation – it does not depend on a numeric utility function. If the preference relation is represented by a utility function and the function is differentiable, then the MRS can be calculated from the derivatives of that function:
MRS=
v'x | |
v'y |
.
v(x,y)=xa ⋅ yb
MRS=
a ⋅ xa-1 ⋅ yb | = | |
b ⋅ yb-1 ⋅ xa |
ay | |
bx |
v(x,y)=a ⋅ log{x}+b ⋅ log{y}
In general, the MRS may be different at different points
(x0,y0)
(9,1)
(9,9)
(1,1)
When the MRS of a certain preference relation does not depend on the bundle, i.e., the MRS is the same for all
(x0,y0)
x+λy=const,
v(x,y)=x+λy.
\sqrt{x+λy}
(x+λy)2
When the MRS depends on
y0
x0
v(x,y)=x+\gammavY(y)
vY
λ(y)
vY
λ(y)
vY(y)=\int
y | |
0 |
{λ(y')dy'}
A more general type of utility function is an additive function:
v(x,y)=vX(x)+vY(y)
There are several ways to check whether given preferences are representable by an additive utility function.
If the preferences are additive then a simple arithmetic calculation shows that
(x1,y1)\succeq(x2,y2)
(x2,y3)\succeq(x3,y1)
(x1,y3)\succeq(x3,y2)
Debreu (1960) showed that this property is also sufficient: i.e., if a preference relation satisfies the double-cancellation property then it can be represented by an additive utility function.[7]
If the preferences are represented by an additive function, then a simple arithmetic calculation shows that
MRS(x2,y
|
When there are three or more commodities, the condition for the additivity of the utility function is surprisingly simpler than for two commodities. This is an outcome of Theorem 3 of Debreu (1960). The condition required for additivity is preferential independence.[5]
A subset A of commodities is said to be preferentially independent of a subset B of commodities, if the preference relation in subset A, given constant values for subset B, is independent of these constant values. For example, suppose there are three commodities: x y and z. The subset is preferentially-independent of the subset, if for all
xi,yi,z,z'
(x1,y1,z)\preceq(x2,y2,z)\iff(x1,y1,z')\preceq(x2,y2,z')
(x1,y1)\preceq(x2,y2)
Preferential independence makes sense in case of independent goods. For example, the preferences between bundles of apples and bananas are probably independent of the number of shoes and socks that an agent has, and vice versa.
By Debreu's theorem, if all subsets of commodities are preferentially independent of their complements, then the preference relation can be represented by an additive value function. Here we provide an intuitive explanation of this result by showing how such an additive value function can be constructed.[5] The proof assumes three commodities: x, y, z. We show how to define three points for each of the three value functions
vx,vy,vz
0 point: choose arbitrary
x0,y0,z0
vx(x0)=vy(y0)=vz(z0)=0
1 point: choose arbitrary
x1>x0
(x1,y0,z0)\succ(x0,y0,z0)
vx(x1)=1
y1
z1
(x1,y0,z0)\sim(x0,y1,z0)\sim(x0,y0,z1)
vy(y1)=vz(z1)=1
2 point: Now we use the preferential-independence assumption. The relation between
(x1,y0)
(x0,y1)
(y1,z0)
(y0,z1)
(z1,x0)
(z0,x1)
(x1,y0,z1)\sim(x0,y1,z1)\sim(x1,y1,z0).
x2,y2,z2
(x2,y0,z0)\sim(x0,y2,z0)\sim(x0,y0,z2)\sim(x1,y1,z0)
vx(x2)=vy(y2)=vz(z2)=2.
3 point: To show that our assignments so far are consistent, we must show that all points that receive a total value of 3 are indifference points. Here, again, the preferential independence assumption is used, since the relation between
(x2,y0)
(x1,y1)
(x2,y0,z1)\sim(x1,y1,z1)
We can continue like this by induction and define the per-commodity functions in all integer points, then use continuity to define it in all real points.
An implicit assumption in point 1 of the above proof is that all three commodities are essential or preference relevant.[7] This means that there exists a bundle such that, if the amount of a certain commodity is increased, the new bundle is strictly better.
The proof for more than 3 commodities is similar. In fact, we do not have to check that all subsets of points are preferentially independent; it is sufficient to check a linear number of pairs of commodities. E.g., if there are
m
j=1,...,m
j=1,...,m-1
\{xj,xj+1\}
m-2
An additive preference relation can be represented by many different additive utility functions. However, all these functions are similar: they are not only increasing monotone transformations of each other (as are all utility functions representing the same relation); they are increasing linear transformations of each other.[7] In short,
An additive ordinal utility function is unique up to increasing linear transformation.
The mathematical foundations of most common types of utility functions — quadratic and additive — laid down by Gérard Debreu[9] [10] enabled Andranik Tangian to develop methods for their construction from purely ordinal data.In particular, additive and quadratic utility functions in
n
n
n-1
The following table compares the two types of utility functions common in economics:
Represents preferences on | Unique up to | Existence proved by | Mostly used in | |||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Ordinal scale | Sure outcomes | Consumer theory under certainty | ||||
Interval scale | Random outcomes (lotteries) | Game theory, choice under uncertainty |