Atom (measure theory) explained
In mathematics, more precisely in measure theory, an atom is a measurable set which has positive measure and contains no set of smaller positive measures. A measure which has no atoms is called non-atomic or atomless.
Definition
and a
measure
on that space, a set
in
is called an
atom if
and for any measurable subset
,
0\in\{\mu(B),\mu(A\setminusB)\}
.
If
is an atom, all the subsets in the
-equivalence class
of
are atoms, and
is called an atomic class. If
is a
-finite measure, there are countably many atomic classes.
Examples
be the
power set of
X. Define the measure
of a set to be its
cardinality, that is, the number of elements in the set. Then, each of the
singletons, for
i = 1, 2, ..., 9, 10 is an atom.
Atomic measures
A
-finite measure
on a
measurable space
is called
atomic or
purely atomic if every measurable set of positive measure contains an atom. This is equivalent to say that there is a
countable partition of
formed by atoms up to a null set.
[1] The assumption of
-finitude is essential. Consider otherwise the space
where
denotes the
counting measure. This space is atomic, with all atoms being the
singletons, yet the space is not able to be partitioned into the disjoint union of countably many disjoint atoms,
and a null set
since the countable union of singletons is a countable set, and the
uncountability of the real numbers shows that the complement
would have to be uncountable, hence its
-measure would be infinite, in contradiction to it being a null set. The validity of the result for
-finite spaces follows from the proof for finite measure spaces by observing that the countable union of countable unions is again a countable union, and that the countable unions of null sets are null.
Discrete measures
See also: Discrete measure. A
-finite atomic measure
is called
discrete if the intersection of the atoms of any atomic class is non empty. It is equivalent
[2] to say that
is the weighted sum of countably many Dirac measures, that is, there is a sequence
of points in
, and a sequence
of positive real numbers (the weights) such that
, which means that
for every
. We can choose each point
to be a common point of the atomsin the
-th atomic class.
A discrete measure is atomic but the inverse implication fails: take
,
the
-algebra of countable and co-countable subsets,
in countable subsets and
in co-countable subsets. Then there is a single atomic class, the one formed by the co-countable subsets. The measure
is atomic but the intersection of the atoms in the unique atomic class is empty and
can't be put as a sum of Dirac measures.
If every atom is equivalent to a singleton, then
is discrete iff it is atomic. In this case the
above are the atomic singletons, so they are unique. Any finite measure in a separable metric space provided with the Borel sets satisfies this condition.
[3] Non-atomic measures
A measure which has no atoms is called or a . In other words, a measure
is non-atomic if for any measurable set
with
there exists a measurable subset
of
such that
A non-atomic measure with at least one positive value has an infinite number of distinct values, as starting with a set
with
one can construct a decreasing sequence of measurable sets
such that
This may not be true for measures having atoms; see the first example above.
It turns out that non-atomic measures actually have a continuum of values. It can be proved that if
is a non-atomic measure and
is a measurable set with
then for any real number
satisfying
there exists a measurable subset
of
such that
This theorem is due to Wacław Sierpiński.[4] [5] It is reminiscent of the intermediate value theorem for continuous functions.
Sketch of proof of Sierpiński's theorem on non-atomic measures. A slightly stronger statement, which however makes the proof easier, is that if
is a non-atomic measure space and
there exists a function
that is monotone with respect to inclusion, and a right-inverse to
That is, there exists a one-parameter family of measurable sets
such that for all
The proof easily follows from
Zorn's lemma applied to the set of all monotone partial sections to
:
ordered by inclusion of graphs,
graph(S)\subseteqgraph(S').
It's then standard to show that every chain in
has an upper bound in
and that any maximal element of
has domain
proving the claim.
See also
Notes
- Web site: Analysis - Countable partition in atoms.
- Web site: Why must a discrete atomic measure admit a decomposition into Dirac measures? Moreover, what is "an atomic class"?.
- Book: Kadets, Vladimir . A Course in Functional Analysis and Measure Theory . 2018 . Springer . Switzerland . 978-3-319-92003-0 . 45.
- W. . Sierpinski . Sur les fonctions d'ensemble additives et continues . Fundamenta Mathematicae . 3 . 240–246 . 1922. 10.4064/fm-3-1-240-246 . fr .
- Book: Fryszkowski, Andrzej. Fixed Point Theory for Decomposable Sets (Topological Fixed Point Theory and Its Applications). 2005. Springer. New York. 1-4020-2498-3. 39.
References
- Book: Bruckner, Andrew M. . Bruckner, Judith B. . Thomson, Brian S. . Real analysis . 1997 . Prentice-Hall . Upper Saddle River, N.J. . 0-13-458886-X . 108 . registration .
- Book: Butnariu, Dan . Klement, E. P. . Triangular norm-based measures and games with fuzzy coalitions . 1993 . Kluwer Academic . Dordrecht . 0-7923-2369-6 . 87.
External links
- Atom at The Encyclopedia of Mathematics