Multiwinner voting explained

Multiwinner,[1] at-large, or committee[2] [3] voting refers to electoral systems that elect several candidates at once. Such methods can be used to elect parliaments or committees.

Goals

There are many scenarios in which multiwinner voting is useful. They can be broadly classified into three classes, based on the main objective in electing the committee:[4]

  1. Excellence. Here, voters judge the quality of each candidate individually. The goal is to find the "objectively" best candidates. An example application is shortlisting: selecting, from a list of candidate employees, a small set of finalists, who will proceed to the final stage of evaluation (e.g. using an interview). Here, each candidate is evaluated independently of the others. If two candidates are similar, then probably both will be elected or both will be rejected.
  2. Diversity. Here, the elected candidates should be as different as possible. For example, suppose the candidates are possible locations for constructing a facility, such as a fire station. Most citizens naturally prefer a fire station in the city center. However, there is no need to have two fire-stations in the same place; it is better to diversify the selection and put the second station in a more remote location. In contrast to the "excellence" setting, if two candidates are similar, then probably exactly one of them will be elected. Another scenario in which diversity is important is when a search engine selects results for display, or when an airline selects movies for screening during a flight.
  3. Proportionality. Here, the elected candidates should represent the diverse opinion held by the population of voters, measured by the votes they cast, as much as possible. This is a common goal in parliamentary elections; see proportional representation.

Families of methods

A major challenge in the study of multiwinner voting is finding reasonable adaptations of concepts from single-winner voting. These can be classified based on the voting type—approval voting vs. ranked voting.

Some election systems elect multiple members by competition held among individual candidates. Such systems are some variations of multiple non-transferable voting and single transferable voting.

In other systems, candidates are grouped in committees (slates) and voters cast votes for the committees (or slates).

Approval voting for committees

See main article: Multiwinner approval voting. Approval voting is a common method for single-winner elections and sometimes for multiwinner elections. In single-winner elections, each voter marks the candidate he approves, and the candidate with the most votes wins.

With multiwinner voting, there are many ways to decide which candidate should be elected. In some, each voter ranks the candidates; in others they cast X votes. As well, each voter may cast single or multiple votes.

Already in 1895, Thiele suggested a family of weight-based rules called Thiele's voting rules.[5] Each rule in the family is defined by a sequence of k weakly-positive weights, w1,...,wk (where k is the committee size). Each voter assigns, to each committee containing p candidates approved by the voter, a score equal to w1+...+wp. The committee with the highest total score is elected. Some common voting rules in Thiele's family are:

There are rules based on other principles, such as minimax approval voting[6] and its generalizations,[7] as well as Phragmen's voting rules[8] and the method of equal shares.[9] [10]

The complexity of determining the winners vary: MNTV winners can be found in polynomial time, while Chamberlin-Courant[11] and PAV are both NP-hard.

Positional scoring rules for committees

Positional scoring rules are common in rank-based single-winner voting. Each voter ranks the candidates from best to worst, a pre-specified function assigns a score to each candidate based on his rank, and the candidate with the highest total score is elected.

In multiwinner voting held using these systems, we need to assign scores to committees rather than to individual candidates. There are various ways to do this, for example:

Condorcet committees

In single-winner voting, a Condorcet winner is a candidate who wins in every head-to-head election against each of the other candidates. A Condorcet method is a method that selects a Condorcet winner whenever it exists. There are several ways to adapt Condorcet's criterion to multiwinner voting:

Excellence elections

Excellence means that the committee should contain the "best" candidates. Excellence-based voting rules are often called screening rules. They are often used as a first step in a selection of a single best candidate, that is, a method for creating a shortlist. A basic property that should be satisfied by such a rule is committee monotonicity (also called house monotonicity, a variant of resource monotonicity): if some k candidates are elected by a rule, and then the committee size increases to k+1 and the rule is re-applied, then the first k candidates should still be elected. Some families of committee-monotone rules are:

The property of committee monotonicity is incompatible with the property of stability (a particular adaptation of Condorcet's criterion): there exists a single voting profile that admits a unique Condorcet set of size 2, and a unique Condorcet set of size 3, and they are disjoint (the set of size 2 is not contained in the set of size 3).

On the other hand, there exists a family of positional scoring rules - the separable positional scoring rules - that are committee-monotone. These rules are also computable in polynomial time (if their underlying single-winner scoring functions are). For example, k-Borda is separable while multiple non-transferable vote is not.

Diversity elections

Diversity means that the committee should contain the top-ranked candidates of as many voters as possible. Formally, the following axioms are reasonable for diversity-centered applications:

Proportional elections

See main article: Justified representation. Proportionality means that each cohesive group of voters (that is: a group of voters with similar preferences) should be represented by a number of winners proportional to its size. Formally, if the committee is of size k, there are n voters, and some L*n/k voters rank the same L candidates at the top (or approve the same L candidates), then these L candidates should be elected. This principle is easy to implement when the voters vote for parties (in party-list systems), but it can also be adapted to approval voting or ranked voting; see justified representation and proportionality for solid coalitions.

See also

References

  1. Elkind. Edith. Faliszewski. Piotr. Skowron. Piotr. Slinko. Arkadii. 2017-03-01. Properties of multiwinner voting rules. Social Choice and Welfare. en. 48. 3. 599–632. 10.1007/s00355-017-1026-z. 1432-217X. 7089675. 32226187.
  2. Aziz. Haris. Brill. Markus. Conitzer. Vincent. Elkind. Edith. Freeman. Rupert. Walsh. Toby. 2017. Justified representation in approval-based committee voting. Social Choice and Welfare. en. 48. 2. 461–485. 10.1007/s00355-016-1019-3. 8564247. 1407.8269.
  3. 1998-05-01. Consensus rules for committee elections. Mathematical Social Sciences. en. 35. 3. 219–232. 10.1016/S0165-4896(97)00033-4. 0165-4896. Bock. Hans-Hermann. Day. William H.E.. McMorris. F.R..
  4. Book: Piotr Faliszewski, Piotr Skowron, Arkadii Slinko, Nimrod Talmon. https://books.google.com/books?id=0qY8DwAAQBAJ&dq=multiwinner++voting+a+new+challenge&pg=PA27. Trends in Computational Social Choice. 2017-10-26. Lulu.com. 978-1-326-91209-3. Endriss. Ulle. en. Multiwinner Voting: A New Challenge for Social Choice Theory.
  5. Sánchez-Fernández. Luis. Elkind. Edith. Lackner. Martin. Fernández. Norberto. Fisteus. Jesús. Val. Pablo Basanta. Skowron. Piotr. 2017-02-10. Proportional Justified Representation. Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. en. 31. 1. 10.1609/aaai.v31i1.10611 . 17538641 . 2374-3468. free. 10016/26166. free.
  6. Brams. Steven J.. Kilgour. D. Marc. Sanver. M. Remzi. 2007-09-01. A minimax procedure for electing committees. Public Choice. en. 132. 3. 401–420. 10.1007/s11127-007-9165-x. 46632580. 1573-7101.
  7. Amanatidis. Georgios. Barrot. Nathanaël. Lang. Jérôme. Markakis. Evangelos. Ries. Bernard. 2015-05-04. Multiple Referenda and Multiwinner Elections Using Hamming Distances: Complexity and Manipulability. Proceedings of the 2015 International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems. AAMAS '15. Istanbul, Turkey. International Foundation for Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems. 715–723. 978-1-4503-3413-6.
  8. Brill. Markus. Freeman. Rupert. Janson. Svante. Lackner. Martin. 2017-02-10. Phragmén's Voting Methods and Justified Representation. Proceedings of the AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence. en. 31. 1. 10.1609/aaai.v31i1.10598 . 2290202 . 2374-3468. free. 2102.12305.
  9. Book: Peters. Dominik. Skowron. Piotr. Proceedings of the 21st ACM Conference on Economics and Computation . Proportionality and the Limits of Welfarism . EC'20. 2020. 793–794. 10.1145/3391403.3399465. 1911.11747. 9781450379755. 208291203.
  10. Pierczyński. Grzegorz. Peters. Dominik. Skowron. Piotr. Proportional Participatory Budgeting with Additive Utilities.. Proceedings of the 2021 Conference on Neural Information Processing Systems. NeurIPS'21. 2021. 2008.13276.
  11. Procaccia. Ariel D.. Rosenschein. Jeffrey S.. Zohar. Aviv. 2007-04-19. On the complexity of achieving proportional representation. Social Choice and Welfare. 30. 3. 353–362. 10.1007/s00355-007-0235-2. 18126521.
  12. Chamberlin. John R.. Courant. Paul N.. 1983. Representative Deliberations and Representative Decisions: Proportional Representation and the Borda Rule. The American Political Science Review. 77. 3. 718–733. 10.2307/1957270. 1957270. 147162169 . 0003-0554.
  13. 1981-10-01. Majority committees. Journal of Economic Theory. en. 25. 2. 255–268. 10.1016/0022-0531(81)90005-3. 0022-0531. Fishburn. Peter C..
  14. Fishburn. Peter C.. 1981-12-01. An Analysis of Simple Voting Systems for Electing Committees. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics. 41. 3. 499–502. 10.1137/0141041. 0036-1399.
  15. 2013-11-01. How hard is it to tell which is a Condorcet committee?. Mathematical Social Sciences. en. 66. 3. 282–292. 10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2013.06.004. 0165-4896. 4376023. Darmann. Andreas. 25843993.
  16. 1985-12-01. The Condorcet criterion and committee selection. Mathematical Social Sciences. en. 10. 3. 199–209. 10.1016/0165-4896(85)90043-5. 0165-4896. Gehrlein. William V..
  17. Ratliff. Thomas C.. 2003-12-01. Some startling inconsistencies when electing committees. Social Choice and Welfare. en. 21. 3. 433–454. 10.1007/s00355-003-0209-y. 36949675. 1432-217X.
  18. Barberà. Salvador. Coelho. Danilo. 2008. How to choose a non-controversial list with k names. Social Choice and Welfare. 31. 1. 79–96. 10.1007/s00355-007-0268-6. 41107910. 16974573. 0176-1714.
  19. Book: Coelho. Danilo. Understanding, evaluating and selecting voting rules through games and axioms. Barberà. Salvador. 2005. Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona. 978-84-689-0967-7. Bellaterra.
  20. 2017-05-01. On stable rules for selecting committees. Journal of Mathematical Economics. en. 70. 36–44. 10.1016/j.jmateco.2017.01.008. 0304-4068. Kamwa. Eric. 125508393 .
  21. Elkind. Edith. Lang. Jérôme. Saffidine. Abdallah. 2015. Condorcet winning sets. Social Choice and Welfare. 44. 3. 493–517. 10.1007/s00355-014-0853-4. 43662603. 31128109. 0176-1714.
  22. Faliszewski. Piotr. Skowron. Piotr. Slinko. Arkadii. Talmon. Nimrod. 2016-07-09. Committee scoring rules: axiomatic classification and hierarchy. Proceedings of the Twenty-Fifth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. IJCAI'16. New York, New York, USA. AAAI Press. 250–256. 978-1-57735-770-4.