In mathematical logic, a superintuitionistic logic is a propositional logic extending intuitionistic logic. Classical logic is the strongest consistent superintuitionistic logic; thus, consistent superintuitionistic logics are called intermediate logics (the logics are intermediate between intuitionistic logic and classical logic).[1]
A superintuitionistic logic is a set L of propositional formulas in a countable set ofvariables pi satisfying the following properties:
1. all axioms of intuitionistic logic belong to L;
2. if F and G are formulas such that F and F → G both belong to L, then G also belongs to L (closure under modus ponens);
3. if F(p1, p2, ..., pn) is a formula of L, and G1, G2, ..., Gn are any formulas, then F(G1, G2, ..., Gn) belongs to L (closure under substitution).Such a logic is intermediate if furthermore
4. L is not the set of all formulas.
There exists a continuum of different intermediate logics and just as many such logics exhibit the disjunction property (DP). Superintuitionistic or intermediate logics form a complete lattice with intuitionistic logic as the bottom and the inconsistent logic (in the case of superintuitionistic logics) or classical logic (in the case of intermediate logics) as the top. Classical logic is the only coatom in the lattice of superintuitionistic logics; the lattice of intermediate logics also has a unique coatom, namely SmL.
The tools for studying intermediate logics are similar to those used for intuitionistic logic, such as Kripke semantics. For example, Gödel–Dummett logic has a simple semantic characterization in terms of total orders. Specific intermediate logics may be given by semantical description.
Others are often given by adding one or more axioms to
Examples include:
= (Double-negation elimination, DNE)
= (Principle of excluded middle, PEM)Generalized variants of the above (but actually equivalent principles over intuitionistic logic) are, respectively,
= (inverse contraposition principle)
= (Pierce's principle PP, compare to Consequentia mirabilis)
= (another schema generalizing Consequentia mirabilis)
= (following from PEM via principle of explosion)
= (a conditional PP)
= (Dirk Gently’s principle, DGP, or linearity)
= (a form of independence of premise IP)
= (Generalized 4th De Morgan's law)
=
= (weak PEM, a.k.a. WPEM)
= (a weak DGP)
= (a variant, with negation, of a form of IP)
= (4th De Morgan's law)
= (a conditional WPEM)
= (the other variant, with negation, of a form of IP)
This list is, for the most part, not any sort of ordering. For example, LC is known not to prove all theorems of SmL, but it does not directly compare in strength to BD2. Likewise, e.g., KP does not compare to SL. The list of equalities for each logic is by no means exhaustive either. For example, as with WPEM and De Morgan's law, several forms of DGP using conjunction may be expressed.
Even (¬¬p ∨ ¬p) ∨ (¬¬p → p), a further weakening of WPEM, is not a theorem of IPC.
It may also be worth noting that, taking all of intuitionistic logic for granted, the equalities notably rely on explosion. For example, over mere minimal logic, as principle PEM is already equivalent to Consequentia mirabilis, but there does not imply the stronger DNE, nor PP, and is not comparable to DGP.
Going on:
LC + BDn−1
= LC + BCn−1
nl(wedge | |
styleIPC+vee | |
j<i |
pj\topir)
nl(wedge | |
styleIPC+vee | |
j<i |
pj\to\neg\negpir)
nl(wedge | |
styleIPC+vee | |
j\nei |
pj\topir)
nl(l(p | |
styleIPC+wedge | |
i\tovee |
j\nepjr)\toveej\nepjr)\tovee
np | |
i |
Furthermore:
\langlelP(X)\setminus\{X\},\subseteq\rangle
The propositional logics SL and KP do have the disjunction property DP. Kleene realizability logic and the strong Medvedev's logic do have it as well. There is no unique maximal logic with DP on the lattice.Note that if a consistent theory validates WPEM but still has independent statements when assuming PEM, then it cannot have DP.
Given a Heyting algebra H, the set of propositional formulas that are valid in H is an intermediate logic. Conversely, given an intermediate logic it is possible to construct its Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra, which is then a Heyting algebra.
An intuitionistic Kripke frame F is a partially ordered set, and a Kripke model M is a Kripke frame with valuation such that
\{x\midM,x\Vdashp\}
See main article: Modal companion. Let A be a propositional formula. The Gödel–Tarski translation of A is defined recursively as follows:
T(pn)=\Boxpn
T(\negA)=\Box\negT(A)
T(A\landB)=T(A)\landT(B)
T(A\veeB)=T(A)\veeT(B)
T(A\toB)=\Box(T(A)\toT(B))
If M is a modal logic extending S4 then ρM = is a superintuitionistic logic, and M is called a modal companion of ρM. In particular:
For every intermediate logic L there are many modal logics M such that L = ρM.