Infinitary logic explained

An infinitary logic is a logic that allows infinitely long statements and/or infinitely long proofs.[1] The concept was introduced by Zermelo in the 1930s.[2]

Some infinitary logics may have different properties from those of standard first-order logic. In particular, infinitary logics may fail to be compact or complete. Notions of compactness and completeness that are equivalent in finitary logic sometimes are not so in infinitary logics. Therefore for infinitary logics, notions of strong compactness and strong completeness are defined. This article addresses Hilbert-type infinitary logics, as these have been extensively studied and constitute the most straightforward extensions of finitary logic. These are not, however, the only infinitary logics that have been formulated or studied.

Considering whether a certain infinitary logic named Ω-logic is complete promises to throw light on the continuum hypothesis.[3]

A word on notation and the axiom of choice

As a language with infinitely long formulae is being presented, it is not possible to write such formulae down explicitly. To get around this problem a number of notational conveniences, which, strictly speaking, are not part of the formal language, are used.

is used to point out an expression that is infinitely long. Where it is unclear, the length of the sequence is noted afterwards. Where this notation becomes ambiguous or confusing, suffixes such as

vee\gamma{A\gamma

} are used to indicate an infinite disjunction over a set of formulae of cardinality

\delta

. The same notation may be applied to quantifiers, for example

\forall\gamma{V\gamma:}

. This is meant to represent an infinite sequence of quantifiers: a quantifier for each

V\gamma

where

\gamma<\delta

.

All usage of suffixes and

are not part of formal infinitary languages.

The axiom of choice is assumed (as is often done when discussing infinitary logic) as this is necessary to have sensible distributivity laws.

Formal languages

A first-order infinitary language

L\alpha,\beta

,

\alpha

regular,

\beta=0

or

\omega\leq\beta\leq\alpha

, has the same set of symbols as a finitary logic and may use all the rules for formation of formulae of a finitary logic together with some additional ones:

A=\{A\gamma|\gamma<\delta<\alpha\}

then

(A0\lorA1\lor)

and

(A0\landA1\land)

are formulae. (In each case the sequence has length

\delta

.)

V=\{V\gamma|\gamma<\delta<\beta\}

and a formula

A0

then

\forallV0:\forallV1(A0)

and

\existsV0:\existsV1(A0)

are formulae. (In each case the sequence of quantifiers has length

\delta

.)

The language may also have function, relation, and predicate symbols of finite arity. Karp also defined languages

L\alpha\beta\omicron\pi

with

\pi\leq\alpha

an infinite cardinal and some more complicated restrictions on

\omicron

that allow for function and predicate symbols of infinite arity, with

\omicron

controlling the maximum arity of a function symbol and

\pi

controlling predicate symbols.

The concepts of free and bound variables apply in the same manner to infinite formulae. Just as in finitary logic, a formula all of whose variables are bound is referred to as a sentence.

Definition of Hilbert-type infinitary logics

T

in infinitary language

L\alpha

is a set of sentences in the logic. A proof in infinitary logic from a theory

T

is a (possibly infinite) sequence of statements that obeys the following conditions: Each statement is either a logical axiom, an element of

T

, or is deduced from previous statements using a rule of inference. As before, all rules of inference in finitary logic can be used, together with an additional one:

A=\{A\gamma|\gamma<\delta<\alpha\}

that have occurred previously in the proof then the statement

\land\gamma{A\gamma

} can be inferred.

If

\beta<\alpha

, forming universal closures may not always be possible, however extra constant symbols may be added for each variable with the resulting satisfiability relation remaining the same. To avoid this, some authors use a different definition of the language

L\alpha,\beta

forbidding formulas from having more than

\beta

free variables.[4]

The logical axiom schemata specific to infinitary logic are presented below. Global schemata variables:

\delta

and

\gamma

such that

0<\delta<\alpha

.

((\land\epsilon{(A\delta\impliesA\epsilon)})\implies(A\delta\implies\land\epsilon{A\epsilon

}))

\gamma<\delta

,

((\land\epsilon{A\epsilon

}) \implies A_)

\gamma

):

(\lor\mu{(\land\delta{A\mu

})}), where

\forall\mu\forall\delta\exists\epsilon<\gamma:A\mu=A\epsilon

or

A\mu=\negA\epsilon

, and

\forallg\in\gamma\gamma\exists\epsilon<\gamma:\{A\epsilon,\negA\epsilon\}\subseteq\{A\mu:\mu<\gamma\}

\gamma<\alpha

,

((\land\mu{(\lor\delta{A\mu

})}) \implies (\lor_)), where

\{\gamma\epsilon:\epsilon<\gamma\gamma\}

is a well ordering of

\gamma\gamma

The last two axiom schemata require the axiom of choice because certain sets must be well orderable. The last axiom schema is strictly speaking unnecessary, as Chang's distributivity laws imply it,[5] however it is included as a natural way to allow natural weakenings to the logic.

Completeness, compactness, and strong completeness

A theory is any set of sentences. The truth of statements in models are defined by recursion and will agree with the definition for finitary logic where both are defined. Given a theory T a sentence is said to be valid for the theory T if it is true in all models of T.

A logic in the language

L\alpha

is complete if for every sentence S valid in every model there exists a proof of S. It is strongly complete if for any theory T for every sentence S valid in T there is a proof of S from T. An infinitary logic can be complete without being strongly complete.

A cardinal

\kappa\omega

is weakly compact when for every theory T in

L\kappa

containing at most

\kappa

many formulas, if every S

\subseteq

T of cardinality less than

\kappa

has a model, then T has a model. A cardinal

\kappa\omega

is strongly compact when for every theory T in

L\kappa

, without restriction on size, if every S

\subseteq

T of cardinality less than

\kappa

has a model, then T has a model.

Concepts expressible in infinitary logic

In the language of set theory the following statement expresses foundation:

\forall\gamma{V\gamma:}\neg\land\gamma{V\gamma\inV\gamma

}.\,

Unlike the axiom of foundation, this statement admits no non-standard interpretations. The concept of well-foundedness can only be expressed in a logic that allows infinitely many quantifiers in an individual statement. As a consequence many theories, including Peano arithmetic, which cannot be properly axiomatised in finitary logic, can be in a suitable infinitary logic. Other examples include the theories of non-archimedean fields and torsion-free groups.[6] These three theories can be defined without the use of infinite quantification; only infinite junctions[7] are needed.

Truth predicates for countable languages are definable in

lL
\omega1,\omega
.[8]

Complete infinitary logics

Two infinitary logics stand out in their completeness. These are the logics of

L\omega

and
L
\omega1,\omega
. The former is standard finitary first-order logic and the latter is an infinitary logic that only allows statements of countable size.

The logic of

L\omega

is also strongly complete, compact and strongly compact.

The logic of

L
\omega1,\omega
fails to be compact, but it is complete (under the axioms given above). Moreover, it satisfies a variant of the Craig interpolation property.

If the logic of

L\alpha,

is strongly complete (under the axioms given above) then

\alpha

is strongly compact (because proofs in these logics cannot use

\alpha

or more of the given axioms).

Sources

Notes and References

  1. Book: Moore, Gregory H. . 1997 . The prehistory of infinitary logic: 1885–1955 . Dalla Chiara . Maria Luisa . Maria Luisa Dalla Chiara . Doets . Kees . Mundici . Daniele . van Benthem . Johan . Johan van Benthem (logician) . Structures and Norms in Science . Springer-Science+Business Media . 105–123 . 10.1007/978-94-017-0538-7_7 . 978-94-017-0538-7.
  2. Kanamori . Akihiro . Akihiro Kanamori . 2004 . Zermelo and set theory . The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic . 10 . 4 . 487–553 . 10.2178/bsl/1102083759 . 22 August 2023.
  3. Book: Woodin, W. Hugh . W. Hugh Woodin . 2011 . The Continuum Hypothesis, the generic-multiverse of sets, and the Ω Conjecture . https://dokumen.tips/documents/the-continuum-hypothesis-the-generic-multiverse-of-logic-continuum-hypothesis.html . Kennedy . Juliette . Juliette Kennedy . Kossak . Roman . Set Theory, Arithmetic, and Foundations of Mathematics: Theorems, Philosophies . Cambridge University Press . 13–42 . 10.1017/CBO9780511910616.003 . 978-0-511-91061-6 . 1 March 2024.
  4. J. L. Bell, "Infinitary Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, revised 2023. Accessed 26 July 2024.
  5. Chang . C. C. . Chen Chung Chang . 1957 . On the representation of α-complete Boolean algebras . . 85 . 1 . 208–218 . 10.1090/S0002-9947-1957-0086792-1 . free.
  6. Web site: Four departures in Mathematics and Physics . Rosinger . Elemer E. . 2010 . 1003.0360 . 10.1.1.760.6726.
  7. Bennett . David W. . 1980 . Junctions . . 21 . 1 . 111–118 . 10.1305/ndjfl/1093882943 . free.
  8. Web site: Inexpressible longing for the intended model . Pogonowski . Jerzy . 10 June 2010 . Zakład Logiki Stosowanej . . 4 . 1 March 2024.