Horror vacui (physics) explained

In philosophy and early physics, horror vacui (Latin: horror of the vacuum) or plenism - commonly stated as "nature abhors a vacuum", for example by Spinoza[1] - is a hypothesis attributed to Aristotle, later criticized by the atomism of Epicurus and Lucretius, that nature contains no vacuums because the denser surrounding material continuum would immediately fill the rarity of an incipient void.[2] Aristotle also argued against the void in a more abstract sense: since a void is merely nothingness, following his teacher Plato, nothingness cannot rightly be said to exist. Furthermore, insofar as a void would be featureless, it could neither be encountered by the senses nor could its supposition lend additional explanatory power. Hero of Alexandria challenged the theory in the first century AD, but his attempts to create an artificial vacuum failed.[3] The theory was debated in the context of 17th-century fluid mechanics, by Thomas Hobbes and Robert Boyle,[4] among others, and through the early 18th century by Sir Isaac Newton and Gottfried Leibniz.[5] [6]

Etymology

Plenism means "fullness", from Latin plēnum, English "plenty", cognate via Proto-Indo-European to "full". In Ancient Greek, the term for the void is τὸ κενόν (to kenón).

History

The idea was restated as "Natura abhorret vacuum" by François Rabelais in his series of books titled Gargantua and Pantagruel in the 1530s.[7] The theory was supported and restated by Galileo Galilei in the early 17th century as "Resistenza del vacuo". Galileo was surprised by the fact that water could not rise above a certain level in an aspiration tube in his suction pump, leading him to conclude that there is a limit to the phenomenon.[8] René Descartes proposed a plenic interpretation of atomism to eliminate the void, which he considered incompatible with his concept of space.[5] The theory was rejected by later scientists, such as Galileo's pupil Evangelista Torricelli, who repeated his experiment with mercury. Blaise Pascal successfully repeated Galileo's and Torricelli's experiment and foresaw no reason why a perfect vacuum could not be achieved in principle.[9] Scottish philosopher Thomas Carlyle mentioned Pascal's experiment in the Edinburgh Encyclopædia in an 1823 article titled "Pascal".[10]

See also

Notes and References

  1. Spinoza's Ethics and De Intellectus Emendatione. JM Dent & Sons / EP Dutton & Co, 1910 [1928], p. 14.
  2. Book: Aristotle . Physics . IV, 6–9 . 2012-07-10 . https://web.archive.org/web/20120402105731/http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/physics/book4.html#section32 . 2012-04-02 . dead .
  3. Book: Genz, Henning . 1999 . 1994 . Nothingness, the Science of Empty Space . registration . translated from German by Karin Heusch . New York . Perseus . 978-0-7382-0610-3 . 48836264 .
  4. Book: S. . Shapin . S. . Schaffer . 2011 . 1989 . Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life . Princeton University Press . 9781400838493 . 9–10.
  5. Encyclopedia: Robert . Rynasiewicz . Edward N. Zalta . 2011 . Newton's Views on Space, Time, and Motion . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Fall 2011 . Descartes, it can be justly said, is the founder of the other main school of the “mechanical philosophy” of the 17th Century, which stood in direct opposition to atomism on the issue of the possibility of a vacuum and which adapted the Aristotelian doctrines on the nature of time, space, and motion to the new world view..
  6. Book: Barrow, J.D. . 2002 . The Book of Nothing: Vacuums, Voids, and the Latest Ideas About the Origins of the Universe . Vintage Series . Vintage . 9780375726095 . 00058894 . 70.
  7. Book: Soukhanov, Anne H.. The Encarta Book of Quotations. 2000. Bloomsbury Publishing Plc. New York, New York. 0-312-23000-1. 780.
  8. Book: René Dugas. A history of mechanics. 9 July 2011. 1988. Courier Dover Publications. 978-0-486-65632-8. 144.
  9. Blaise Pascal, Experiences nouvelles touchant le vide. [New experiments with the vacuum] (1647).
  10. Book: Carlyle, Thomas. Sartor Resartus, The Life and Opinions of Herr Teufelsdröckh in Three Books. 2000. University of California Press. Berkeley and Los Angeles, California. 0-520-20928-1. 282.