Finite set explained
In mathematics, particularly set theory, a finite set is a set that has a finite number of elements. Informally, a finite set is a set which one could in principle count and finish counting. For example,is a finite set with five elements. The number of elements of a finite set is a natural number (possibly zero) and is called the cardinality (or the cardinal number) of the set. A set that is not a finite set is called an infinite set. For example, the set of all positive integers is infinite:Finite sets are particularly important in combinatorics, the mathematical study of counting. Many arguments involving finite sets rely on the pigeonhole principle, which states that there cannot exist an injective function from a larger finite set to a smaller finite set.
Definition and terminology
Formally, a set
is called
finite if there exists a
bijectionfor some natural number
(natural numbers are defined as sets in
Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory). The number
is the set's cardinality, denoted as
.
If a set is finite, its elements may be written — in many ways — in a sequence:In combinatorics, a finite set with
elements is sometimes called an
-set and a
subset with
elements is called a
-subset. For example, the set
is a 3-set – a finite set with three elements – and
is a 2-subset of it.
Basic properties
Any proper subset of a finite set
is finite and has fewer elements than
S itself. As a consequence, there cannot exist a
bijection between a finite set
S and a proper subset of
S. Any set with this property is called
Dedekind-finite. Using the standard
ZFC axioms for
set theory, every Dedekind-finite set is also finite, but this implication cannot be
proved in ZF (Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms without the
axiom of choice) alone.The
axiom of countable choice, a weak version of the axiom of choice, is sufficient to prove this equivalence.
Any injective function between two finite sets of the same cardinality is also a surjective function (a surjection). Similarly, any surjection between two finite sets of the same cardinality is also an injection.
The union of two finite sets is finite, with
In fact, by the inclusion–exclusion principle:More generally, the union of any finite number of finite sets is finite. The Cartesian product of finite sets is also finite, with:Similarly, the Cartesian product of finitely many finite sets is finite. A finite set with
elements has
distinct subsets. That is, the
power set
of a finite set
S is finite, with cardinality
.
Any subset of a finite set is finite. The set of values of a function when applied to elements of a finite set is finite.
All finite sets are countable, but not all countable sets are finite. (Some authors, however, use "countable" to mean "countably infinite", so do not consider finite sets to be countable.)
The free semilattice over a finite set is the set of its non-empty subsets, with the join operation being given by set union.
Necessary and sufficient conditions for finiteness
In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice (ZF), the following conditions are all equivalent:[1]
is a finite set. That is,
can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence with the set of those natural numbers less than some specific natural number.
- (Kazimierz Kuratowski)
has all properties which can be proved by mathematical induction beginning with the empty set and adding one new element at a time.
- (Paul Stäckel)
can be given a
total ordering which is
well-ordered both forwards and backwards. That is, every non-empty subset of
has both a least and a greatest element in the subset.
- Every one-to-one function from
into itself is
onto. That is, the
powerset of the powerset of
is Dedekind-finite (see below).
[2] - Every surjective function from
onto itself is one-to-one.
- (Alfred Tarski) Every non-empty family of subsets of
has a
minimal element with respect to inclusion.
[3] (Equivalently, every non-empty family of subsets of
has a
maximal element with respect to inclusion.)
can be well-ordered and any two well-orderings on it are
order isomorphic. In other words, the well-orderings on
have exactly one
order type.
If the axiom of choice is also assumed (the axiom of countable choice is sufficient),[4] then the following conditions are all equivalent:
is a finite set.
- (Richard Dedekind) Every one-to-one function from
into itself is onto. A set with this property is called
Dedekind-finite.
- Every surjective function from
onto itself is one-to-one.
is empty or every
partial ordering of
contains a
maximal element.
Other concepts of finiteness
In ZF set theory without the axiom of choice, the following concepts of finiteness for a set
are distinct. They are arranged in strictly decreasing order of strength, i.e. if a set
meets a criterion in the list then it meets all of the following criteria. In the absence of the axiom of choice the reverse implications are all unprovable, but if the axiom of choice is assumed then all of these concepts are equivalent.
[5] (Note that none of these definitions need the set of finite
ordinal numbers to be defined first; they are all pure "set-theoretic" definitions in terms of the equality and membership relations, not involving ω.)
- I-finite. Every non-empty set of subsets of
has a
-maximal element. (This is equivalent to requiring the existence of a
-minimal element. It is also equivalent to the standard numerical concept of finiteness.)
- Ia-finite. For every partition of
into two sets, at least one of the two sets is I-finite. (A set with this property which is not I-finite is called an
amorphous set.)
- II-finite. Every non-empty
-monotone set of subsets of
has a
-maximal element.
- III-finite. The power set
is Dedekind finite.
is Dedekind finite.
or
.
or
or
.
is I-finite or not well-orderable.
The forward implications (from strong to weak) are theorems within ZF. Counter-examples to the reverse implications (from weak to strong) in ZF with urelements are found using model theory.[6]
Most of these finiteness definitions and their names are attributed to by . However, definitions I, II, III, IV and V were presented in, together with proofs (or references to proofs) for the forward implications. At that time, model theory was not sufficiently advanced to find the counter-examples.
Each of the properties I-finite thru IV-finite is a notion of smallness in the sense that any subset of a set with such a property will also have the property. This is not true for V-finite thru VII-finite because they may have countably infinite subsets.
See also
References
- Book: Howard. Paul. Rubin. Jean E.. Jean E. Rubin . Consequences of the axiom of choice. registration. 1998. American Mathematical Society. Providence, Rhode Island. 9780821809778.
- Lévy . Azriel . Azriel Lévy. 1958 . The independence of various definitions of finiteness . . 46 . 1–13 . 10.4064/fm-46-1-1-13 . https://web.archive.org/web/20030705012432/http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/fm/fm46/fm4611.pdf . 2003-07-05 . live. free .
- Tarski . Alfred . Alfred Tarski . 1924 . Sur les ensembles finis . . 6 . 45–95 . 10.4064/fm-6-1-45-95 . https://web.archive.org/web/20110515012755/http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/fm/fm6/fm619.pdf . 2011-05-15 . live . free .
- Tarski . Alfred . Alfred Tarski . 1954 . Theorems on the existence of successors of cardinals, and the axiom of choice. Nederl. Akad. Wetensch. Proc. Ser. A, Indagationes Math. . 16. 26–32. 10.1016/S1385-7258(54)50005-3 . 0060555.
- Book: Whitehead. Alfred North. Alfred North Whitehead. Russell. Bertrand. Bertrand Russell. February 2009. 1912. Principia Mathematica. Two. Merchant Books. 978-1-60386-183-0.
Notes and References
- Web site: Art of Problem Solving . 2022-09-07 . artofproblemsolving.com.
- The equivalence of the standard numerical definition of finite sets to the Dedekind-finiteness of the power set of the power set was shown in 1912 by . This Whitehead/Russell theorem is described in more modern language by .
- , demonstrated that his definition (which is also known as I-finite) is equivalent to Kuratowski's set-theoretical definition, which he then noted is equivalent to the standard numerical definition via the proof by .
- Book: Herrlich . Horst . Axiom of Choice . 2006 . Springer . Lecture Notes in Mathematics . 1876 . 10.1007/11601562 . 3-540-30989-6 . 18 July 2023. Proposition 4.13. 48.
- This list of 8 finiteness concepts is presented with this numbering scheme by both, and, although the details of the presentation of the definitions differ in some respects which do not affect the meanings of the concepts.
- found counter-examples to each of the reverse implications in Mostowski models. Lévy attributes most of the results to earlier papers by Mostowski and Lindenbaum.