In mathematics, the epsilon numbers are a collection of transfinite numbers whose defining property is that they are fixed points of an exponential map. Consequently, they are not reachable from 0 via a finite series of applications of the chosen exponential map and of "weaker" operations like addition and multiplication. The original epsilon numbers were introduced by Georg Cantor in the context of ordinal arithmetic; they are the ordinal numbers ε that satisfy the equation
\varepsilon=\omega\varepsilon,
in which ω is the smallest infinite ordinal.
The least such ordinal is ε0 (pronounced epsilon nought (chiefly British), epsilon naught (chiefly American), or epsilon zero), which can be viewed as the "limit" obtained by transfinite recursion from a sequence of smaller limit ordinals:
\varepsilon0=
| |||||||||||||
\omega |
=\sup\left\{\omega,\omega\omega,
\omega\omega | |
\omega |
,
| |||||
\omega |
,...\right\},
Larger ordinal fixed points of the exponential map are indexed by ordinal subscripts, resulting in
\varepsilon1,\varepsilon2,\ldots,\varepsilon\omega,\varepsilon\omega+1,\ldots,
\varepsilon | |
\varepsilon0 |
,\ldots,
\varepsilon | |
\varepsilon1 |
,\ldots,
\varepsilon | |||||||||||||
|
,\ldots
The smallest epsilon number appears in many induction proofs, because for many purposes transfinite induction is only required up to (as in Gentzen's consistency proof and the proof of Goodstein's theorem). Its use by Gentzen to prove the consistency of Peano arithmetic, along with Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, show that Peano arithmetic cannot prove the well-foundedness of this ordering (it is in fact the least ordinal with this property, and as such, in proof-theoretic ordinal analysis, is used as a measure of the strength of the theory of Peano arithmetic).
Many larger epsilon numbers can be defined using the Veblen function.
A more general class of epsilon numbers has been identified by John Horton Conway and Donald Knuth in the surreal number system, consisting of all surreals that are fixed points of the base ω exponential map .
defined gamma numbers (see additively indecomposable ordinal) to be numbers such that whenever, and delta numbers (see multiplicatively indecomposable ordinal) to be numbers such that whenever, and epsilon numbers to be numbers such that whenever . His gamma numbers are those of the form, and his delta numbers are those of the form .
The standard definition of ordinal exponentiation with base α is:
\alpha0=1,
\alpha\beta=\alpha\beta-1 ⋅ \alpha,
\beta
\beta-1
\alpha\beta=\sup\lbrace\alpha\delta\mid0<\delta<\beta\rbrace
\beta
\beta\mapsto\alpha\beta
\alpha=\omega
\varepsilon0=\sup\left\lbrace1,\omega,\omega\omega,
\omega\omega | |
\omega |
,
| |||||
\omega |
,\ldots\right\rbrace,
\varepsilon\beta=\sup\left\lbrace{\varepsilon\beta-1+1},
\varepsilon\beta-1+1 | |
\omega |
,
| |||||
\omega |
,
| |||||||||
\omega |
,\ldots\right\rbrace,
\beta
\beta-1
\varepsilon\beta=\sup\lbrace\varepsilon\delta\mid\delta<\beta\rbrace
\beta
Because
\varepsilon0+1 | |
\omega |
=
\varepsilon0 | |
\omega |
⋅ \omega1=\varepsilon0 ⋅ \omega,
| |||||
\omega |
=
(\varepsilon0 ⋅ \omega) | |
\omega |
=
\varepsilon0 | |
{(\omega |
)}\omega=
\omega | |
\varepsilon | |
0 |
,
| |||||||||
\omega |
=
{\varepsilon0 | |
\omega |
\omega}=
{\varepsilon0 | |
\omega |
1+\omega
\varepsilon1
\varepsilon1=\sup\left\{1,\varepsilon0,
\varepsilon0 | |
{\varepsilon | |
0} |
,
{\varepsilon0 | |
{\varepsilon | |
0} |
\varepsilon0 | |
Generally, the epsilon number
\varepsilon\beta
\beta-1
\varepsilon\beta=\sup\left\{1,\varepsilon\beta-1,
\varepsilon\beta-1 | |
\varepsilon | |
\beta-1 |
,
| |||||||
\varepsilon | |||||||
\beta-1 |
,...\right\}.
\varepsilon\beta
1<\delta<\varepsilon\beta
Since the epsilon numbers are an unbounded subclass of the ordinal numbers, they are enumerated using the ordinal numbers themselves. For any ordinal number
\beta
\varepsilon\beta
\{\varepsilon\delta\mid\delta<\beta\}
The following facts about epsilon numbers are straightforward to prove:
\varepsilon0
\varepsilon\beta
\beta
\beta\mapsto\varepsilon\beta
\varepsilon=\omega\varepsilon
\alpha<\varepsilon0
\beta1 | |
\alpha=\omega |
\beta2 | |
+\omega |
\betak | |
+ … +\omega |
\beta1,\ldots,\betak
\alpha>\beta1\geq … \geq\betak
\alpha
\beta1,\ldots,\betak
\beta1,\ldots,\betak
1=\omega0
This representation is related to the proof of the hydra theorem, which represents decreasing sequences of ordinals as a graph-theoretic game.
See main article: Veblen function. The fixed points of the "epsilon mapping"
x\mapsto\varepsilonx
Continuing in this vein, one can define maps for progressively larger ordinals α (including, by this rarefied form of transfinite recursion, limit ordinals), with progressively larger least fixed points . The least ordinal not reachable from 0 by this procedure—i. e., the least ordinal α for which, or equivalently the first fixed point of the map
\alpha\mapsto\varphi\alpha(0)
\alpha\mapsto\varphi\alpha(0)
n\mapsto\omegan
It is natural to consider any fixed point of this expanded map to be an epsilon number, whether or not it happens to be strictly an ordinal number. Some examples of non-ordinal epsilon numbers are
\varepsilon-1=\left\{0,1,\omega,\omega\omega,\ldots\mid\varepsilon0-1,
\varepsilon0-1 | |
\omega |
,\ldots\right\}
and
\varepsilon1/2=\left\{\varepsilon0+1,
\varepsilon0+1 | |
\omega |
,\ldots\mid\varepsilon1-1,
\varepsilon1-1 | |
\omega |
,\ldots\right\}.
There is a natural way to define
\varepsilonn