Epistemic injustice explained

Epistemic injustice is injustice related to knowledge. It includes exclusion and silencing; systematic distortion or misrepresentation of one's meanings or contributions; undervaluing of one's status or standing in communicative practices; unfair distinctions in authority; and unwarranted distrust.[1]

An influential theory of epistemic injustice is that of British philosopher Miranda Fricker, who coined the term in 1999.[2] According to Fricker, there are two kinds of epistemic injustice: testimonial injustice and hermeneutical injustice.[3]

Related concepts include epistemic oppression and epistemic violence.

Origins

Though the term epistemic injustice was not coined until 1999, prior philosophers have posited similar concepts.

Vivian May has argued that civil rights activist Anna Julia Cooper in the 1890s anticipated the concept in claiming that Black women are denied full and equal recognition as knowers.[4]

Gaile Pohlhaus Jr. points to Gayatri Chakrovorty Spivak's 1988 essay "Can the Subaltern Speak?" as another anticipation. In that essay, Spivak describes what she calls epistemic violence occurring when subaltern persons are prevented from speaking for themselves about their own interests because of others claiming to know what those interests are.

Testimonial injustice

Testimonial injustice is unfairness related to trusting someone's word. An injustice of this kind can occur when someone is ignored, or not believed, because of their sex, sexuality, gender presentation, race, disability, or, broadly, because of their identity.

Miranda Fricker gives the example of Londoner Duwayne Brooks, who saw his friend Stephen Lawrence murdered.[5] The police officers who arrived at the scene regarded Brooks with suspicion. According to an official inquiry, "the officers failed to concentrate upon Mr. Brooks and to follow up energetically the information which he gave them. Nobody suggested that he should accompany them in searches of the area, although he knew where the assailants had last been seen. Nobody appears properly to have tried to calm him, or to accept that what he said was true."[6] That is, the police officers failed to view Brooks as a credible witness, presumably in part due to racial bias. This was, says Fricker, a case of testimonial injustice, which occurs when "prejudice causes a hearer to give a deflated level of credibility to a speaker’s word."[7]

Hermeneutical injustice

Hermeneutical injustice is injustice caused by people being unable to make sense of certain experiences in their life, owing to a lack of hermeneutical/interpretive resources required to make sense of the experience. (The word hermeneutical comes from the Greek word for 'interpreter'.)

Hermeneutical injustice occurs when someone's experiences are not well understood — by themselves or by others — because these experiences do not fit any concepts known to them (or known to others), due to the historic exclusion of some groups of people from activities, such as scholarship and journalism, that shape the language people use to make sense of their experiences.

For example, in the 1970s, the phrase sexual harassment was introduced to describe something that many people, especially women, had long experienced.[8] Before this time, a woman experiencing sexual harassment may have had difficulty putting her experience into words. Fricker states that this difficulty is also not accidental, and was largely due to women's exclusion from shaping the English language and participating equally in journalism, publishing, academia, law, and the other institutions and industries that help people make sense of their lives. After the term sexual harassment was introduced, the same woman who experienced sexual harassment may have understood better what happened to her; however, she may have struggled to explain this experience to someone else, because the concept of sexual harassment was not yet well known.

Fricker argues that some women's lives are less intelligible – to themselves, and/or to others – because women have historically wielded less power to shape the categories through which people understand the world.

Epistemological violence

Epistemological violence is distinct from epistemic injustice in that it usually occurs in the power structure of academic research, such as when interpreting empirical results in psychology. Epistemological violence is theoretical interpretations of empirical results that construct a targeted group as inferior, despite alternative and equally viable interpretations of the data.[9]

For example, Dr. Monique Danielle Botha argues that academic studies of Theory of Mind in autistic children constitutes epistemological violence, due to foundational studies explicitly or implicitly drawing universal conclusions about the entire group of autistic people.[10]

Further developments

Other scholars since Fricker have adapted the concept of epistemic injustice and/or expanded what the term includes. These contributions have included naming and narrowing down forms of epistemic injustice, such as epistemic oppression,[11] epistemicide,[12] epistemic exploitation,[13] silencing as testimonial quieting and as testimonial smothering,[14] contributory injustice,[15] distributive epistemic injustice,[16] epistemic trust injustice,[17] and expressive hermeneutical injustice.[18]

José Medina has advocated for an account of epistemic injustice that incorporates more voices and pays attention to context and the relationships at play.[19] Elizabeth S. Anderson has argued that attention should be given to the structural causes and structural remedies of epistemic injustice.[20] A closely related literature on epistemologies of ignorance has also been developing, which has included the identification of overlapping concepts such as white ignorance[21] [22] and willful hermeneutical ignorance.[23]

American philosopher Kristie Dotson has warned that some definitions could leave out important contributions to the ongoing discussion around epistemic injustice. Gaile Pohlhaus Jr. has replied that the concept should therefore be considered an open one, and many different approaches to the concept should be considered.

In 2017, the Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice was published, compiling chapters addressing both the theoretical work on the concept and efforts to apply that theory to practical case studies.[24] The Indian political theorist Rajeev Bhargava uses the term epistemic injustice to describe how colonized groups were wronged when colonizing powers replaced, or negatively impacted, the concepts and categories that colonized groups used to understand themselves and the world.[25] Similarly, in 2021, Professor Dr. Sabelo J. Ndlovu-Gatsheni mentions the term epistemicide and the Cognitive Empire[26] to describe the discrimination of scholars and intellectuals from the Global South by Western academia and in the sphere of decolonisation studies. In 2021 as well, Bhakuni & Abimbola's application of the concept of pose (or the positionality of the speaker) and gaze (the influence of the audience being addressed)[27] as important modifiers of the both credibility deficit (that is, credibility deficit may apply to a person's pose or their role as gaze) and hermeneutical marginalization (that is, a person may be marginalized in relation to their pose as a speaker or to the gaze/audience to whom they have to address themself).[28]

A policy analysis indicated that the World Health Organization definition of neglected tropical disease reflects a form of epistemic injustice, where conditions like snakebite are forced to be framed as a medical condition, resulting in lack of focus on prevention.[29]

Genocide denial has been considered an example of epistemic injustice.[30] [31] [32]

See also

Selected philosophers and theorists

References

Bibliography

Notes and References

  1. Kidd, Ian James, José Medina, Gaile Pohlhaus Jr., eds. The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice (1st ed.). Routledge. . . p. 1.

    "Epistemic injustice refers to those forms of unfair treatment that relate to issues of knowledge, understanding, and participation in communicative practices. These issues include a wide range of topics concerning wrongful treatment and unjust structures in meaning-making and knowledge producing practices, such as the following: exclusion and silencing; invisibility and inaudibility (or distorted presence or representation); having one’s meanings or contributions systematically distorted, misheard, or misrepresented; having diminished status or standing in communicative practices; unfair differentials in authority and/or epistemic agency; being unfairly distrusted; receiving no or minimal uptake; being coopted or instrumentalized; being marginalized as a result of dysfunctional dynamics; etc."

  2. Book: Pohlhaus Jr.. Gaile. Kidd. Ian James. Medina. José. José Medina (philosopher). Pohlhaus Jr.. Gaile. Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice. 2017. Routledge. 978-1-138-82825-4. 13–26. Varieties of Epistemic Injustice. 10.4324/9781315212043.
  3. Book: Fricker, Miranda. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. 2007. Oxford University Press. 978-0-19-823790-7. 1. 729949179.
  4. May . Vivian M. . 2013-10-11 . "Speaking into the Void"? Intersectionality Critiques and Epistemic Backlash . Hypatia . 29 . 1 . 94–112 . 10.1111/hypa.12060 . 145513018.
  5. Web site: Fricker. Miranda. Epistemic Equality?. YouTube. 2014. University of Cape Town, Cape Town, South Africa.
  6. Web site: 21 April 2005 . Opinions of the Lords of Appeal for Judgement in the Cause: Brooks (FC) (Respondent) v. Commissioner of Police for the Metropolis (Appellant) and others .
  7. Auerback . Raymond . 2021-08-08 . Just How Testimonial, Epistemic, Or Correctable Is Testimonial Injustice? . International Journal of Philosophical Studies . en . 29 . 4 . 559–576 . 10.1080/09672559.2021.1997394 . 0967-2559. 10871/128037 . free .
  8. Web site: Until 1975, 'Sexual Harassment' Was the Menace With No Name . 2020-10-08 . history.com. Erin. Blakemore. January 8, 2018.
  9. [Thomas Teo|Teo, Thomas]
  10. M Botha. "Autistic community connectedness as a buffer against the effects of minority stress." (2020)

    "I will argue that literature regarding “theory of mind” has constituted EV. Researchers, based on one experiment, with a small sample of autistic children (20) (mean chronological age = 11, estimated verbal ability age = 5), argued that autistic individuals lacked “theory of mind”, which is to say, they lacked the ability to infer their own and others minds, that this was a universal effect and unique to autism (Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985). Four autistic participants (20%) passed the experiment, demonstrating theory of mind, sixteen did not, yet it was claimed to be a universal effect which was unique to autism. It was hypothesised instead that the kids who passed may not “really” be autistic, instead of theory of mind having limits in its ability to explain autism. The available evidence has never been that it was universal (autistic children who passed the test were deemed to be outliers and an exception to rule, despite making up between 20-25% of the sample completing the task, reliably (Baron-Cohen, Leslie, & Frith, 1985; Yirmiya et al., 1998)."

  11. 10.1080/02691728.2013.782585. Conceptualizing Epistemic Oppression. 2014. Dotson. Kristie. Social Epistemology. 28. 2. 115–138. 144330822.
  12. Book: Santos, Boaventura de Sousa. Epistemologies of the South: Justice Against Epistemicide. 2015-11-16. Routledge. 978-1-315-63487-6. New York. 10.4324/9781315634876.
  13. 10.3998/ergo.12405314.0003.022. Epistemic Exploitation. 2016. Berenstain. Nora. Ergo, an Open Access Journal of Philosophy. 3. 20200916. free.
  14. 10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01177.x. Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing. 2011. Dotson. Kristie. Hypatia. 26. 2. 236–257. 144313735 .
  15. 10.5250/fronjwomestud.33.1.0024. A Cautionary Tale: On Limiting Epistemic Oppression. 2012. Kristie . Dotson. Frontiers: A Journal of Women Studies. 33. 24. 142869935.
  16. Coady . David . 2010 . Two Concepts of Epistemic Injustice . Episteme . en . 7 . 2 . 101–113 . 10.3366/E1742360010000845 . 145332158.
  17. Book: Grasswick, Heidi. Epistemic Injustice in Science . Kidd. Ian James. Medina. José. José Medina (philosopher). Pohlhaus Jr.. Gaile. Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice. 2017. Routledge. 978-1-138-82825-4. 10.4324/9781315212043.
  18. Catala . Amandine . Faucher . Luc . Poirier . Pierre . 2021-05-11 . Autism, epistemic injustice, and epistemic disablement: a relational account of epistemic agency . Synthese . 199 . 3–4 . 9013–9039 . 10.1007/s11229-021-03192-7 . 236566456 . 0039-7857.
  19. 10.1080/02691728.2011.652214. Hermeneutical Injustice and Polyphonic Contextualism: Social Silences and Shared Hermeneutical Responsibilities. 2012. Medina. José. Social Epistemology. 26. 2. 201–220. 16890075.
  20. 10.1080/02691728.2011.652211. Epistemic Justice as a Virtue of Social Institutions. 2012. Anderson. Elizabeth. Social Epistemology. 26. 2. 163–173. 145350986.
  21. Book: Mills, Charles. Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance. 978-0-7914-7101-2. Sullivan. Shannon. Tuana. Nancy. 2007. Albany, NY. SUNY Press. Philosophy and Race Series. 13–38. White Ignorance. https://shifter-magazine.com/wp-content/uploads/2015/10/mills-white-ignorance.pdf.
  22. Book: Mills, Charles. Ideology . Kidd. Ian James. Medina. José. José Medina (philosopher). Pohlhaus Jr.. Gaile. Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice. 2017. Routledge. 978-1-138-82825-4. 10.4324/9781315212043.
  23. 10.1111/j.1527-2001.2011.01222.x. Relational Knowing and Epistemic Injustice: Toward a Theory of Willful Hermeneutical Ignorance. 2012. Pohlhaus. Gaile. Hypatia. 27. 4. 715–735. 143723579 .
  24. Book: Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Injustice. 2017. Routledge. 978-1-138-82825-4. Kidd. Ian James. 10.4324/9781315212043. Medina. José. José Medina (philosopher). Pohlhaus Jr.. Gaile.
  25. Bhargava. Rajeev. 2013. Overcoming the Epistemic Injustice of Colonialism. Global Policy. 4. 4. 413–417. 10.1111/1758-5899.12093.
  26. Ndlovu-Gatsheni. Sabelo J.. 2021-05-04. The cognitive empire, politics of knowledge and African intellectual productions: reflections on struggles for epistemic freedom and resurgence of decolonisation in the twenty-first century. Third World Quarterly. 42. 5. 882–901. 10.1080/01436597.2020.1775487. 225573395 . 0143-6597.
  27. Abimbola . Seye . October 2019 . The foreign gaze: authorship in academic global health . BMJ Global Health . en . 4 . 5 . e002068 . 10.1136/bmjgh-2019-002068 . 2059-7908 . 6830280 . 31750005.
  28. Bhakuni . Himani . Abimbola . Seye . October 2021 . Epistemic injustice in academic global health . The Lancet Global Health . en . 9 . 10 . e1465–e1470 . 10.1016/S2214-109X(21)00301-6. 34384536 . free .
  29. Bhaumik . Soumyadeep . Zwi . Anthony B. . Norton . Robyn . Jagnoor . Jagnoor . 2023-08-01 . How and why snakebite became a global health priority: a policy analysis . BMJ Global Health . en . 8 . 8 . e011923 . 10.1136/bmjgh-2023-011923 . 2059-7908 . 37604596. 10445399 .
  30. Book: Altanian. Melanie. https://brill.com/view/book/edcoll/9789004388000/BP000021.xml. Genocide Denialism as an Intergenerational Injustice. Intergenerational Equity: Environmental and Cultural Concerns. Brill. 2019. 978-90-04-38800-0. Cottier. Thomas. 151–162. en. Lalani. Shaheeza. Siziba. Clarence.
  31. Altanian. Melanie. 2021-03-04. Genocide Denial as Testimonial Oppression. Social Epistemology. 35. 2. 133–146. 10.1080/02691728.2020.1839810. 229073471 . 0269-1728.
  32. Oranlı . Imge . Epistemic Injustice from Afar : Rethinking the Denial of Armenian Genocide . Social Epistemology . 2021 . 35 . 2 . 120–132 . 10.1080/02691728.2020.1839593. 229463301 .