Dynamic epistemic logic explained
Dynamic epistemic logic (DEL) is a logical framework dealing with knowledge and information change. Typically, DEL focuses on situations involving multiple agents and studies how their knowledge changes when events occur. These events can change factual properties of the actual world (they are called ontic events): for example a red card is painted in blue. They can also bring about changes of knowledge without changing factual properties of the world (they are called epistemic events): for example a card is revealed publicly (or privately) to be red. Originally, DEL focused on epistemic events. We only present in this entry some of the basic ideas of the original DEL framework; more details about DEL in general can be found in the references.
Due to the nature of its object of study and its abstract approach, DEL is related and has applications to numerous research areas, such as computer science (artificial intelligence), philosophy (formal epistemology), economics (game theory) and cognitive science. In computer science, DEL is for example very much related to multi-agent systems, which are systems where multiple intelligent agents interact and exchange information.
As a combination of dynamic logic and epistemic logic, dynamic epistemic logic is a young field of research. It really started in 1989 with Plaza's logic of public announcement.[1] Independently, Gerbrandy and Groeneveld[2] proposed a system dealing moreover with private announcement and that was inspired by the work of Veltman.[3] Another system was proposed by van Ditmarsch whose main inspiration was the Cluedo game.[4] But the most influential and original system was the system proposed by Baltag, Moss and Solecki.[5] This system can deal with all the types of situations studied in the works above and its underlying methodology is conceptually grounded. We will present in this entry some of its basic ideas.
Formally, DEL extends ordinary epistemic logic by the inclusion of event models to describe actions, and a product update operator that defines how epistemic models are updated as the consequence of executing actions described through event models. Epistemic logic will first be recalled. Then, actions and events will enter into the picture and we will introduce the DEL framework.[6]
Epistemic Logic
Epistemic logic is a modal logic dealing with the notions of knowledge and belief. As a logic, it is concerned with understanding the process of reasoning about knowledge and belief: which principles relating the notions of knowledge and belief are intuitively plausible? Like epistemology, it stems from the Greek word
\epsilon\pi\iota\sigma\tauη\muη
or ‘episteme’ meaning knowledge.
Epistemology is nevertheless more concerned with analyzing the very
nature and
scope of knowledge, addressing questions such as “What is the definition of knowledge?” or “How is knowledge acquired?”. In fact, epistemic logic grew out of epistemology in the Middle Ages thanks to the efforts of Burley and Ockham.
[7] The formal work, based on modal logic, that inaugurated contemporary research into epistemic logic dates back only to 1962 and is due to
Hintikka.
[8] It then sparked in the 1960s discussions about the principles of knowledge and belief and many axioms for these notions were proposed and discussed.
[9] For example, the interaction axioms
and
are often considered to be intuitive principles: if an agent Knows
then (s)he also Believes
, or if an agent Believes
, then (s)he Knows that (s)he Believes
. More recently, these kinds of philosophical theories were taken up by researchers in
economics,
[10] artificial intelligence and
theoretical computer science[11] where reasoning about knowledge is a central topic. Due to the new setting in which epistemic logic was used, new perspectives and new features such as
computability issues were then added to the research agenda of epistemic logic.
Syntax
In the sequel,
is a finite set whose elements are called agents and
is a set of propositional letters.
The epistemic language is an extension of the basic multi-modal language of modal logic with a common knowledge operator
and a
distributed knowledge operator
. Formally, the
epistemic language
}^ is defined inductively by the following
grammar in
BNF:
}^:\phi~~::=~~ p~\mid~\neg\phi~\mid~(\phi\land\phi)~\mid~K_j\phi~\mid~ C_\phi ~\mid~ D_\phi
where
,
and
. The
basic epistemic language
is the language
without the common knowledge and distributed knowledge operators. The formula
is an abbreviation for
(for a given
),
is an abbreviation for
,
is an abbreviation for
and
an abbreviation for
.
Group notions: general, common and distributed knowledge.
In a multi-agent setting there are three important epistemic concepts: general knowledge, distributed knowledge and common knowledge. The notion of common knowledge was first studied by Lewis in the context of conventions.[12] It was then applied to distributed systems and to game theory,[13] where it allows to express that the rationality of the players, the rules of the game and the set of players are commonly known.
General knowledge.
General knowledge of
means that everybody in the group of agents
knows that
. Formally, this corresponds to the following formula:
E\phi:=\underset{j\in{AGTS}}wedgeKj\phi.
Common knowledge.
Common knowledge of
means that everybody knows
but also that everybody knows that everybody knows
, that everybody knows that everybody knows that everybody knows
, and so on
ad infinitum. Formally, this corresponds to the following formula
C\phi:=E\phi\landEE\phi\landEEE\phi\land\ldots
As we do not allow infinite conjunction the notion of common knowledge will have to be introduced as a primitive in our language.
Before defining the language with this new operator, we are going to give an example introduced by Lewis that illustrates the difference between the notions of general knowledge and common knowledge. Lewis wanted to know what kind of knowledge is needed so that the statement
: “every driver must drive on the right” be a convention among a group of agents. In other words, he wanted to know what kind of knowledge is needed so that everybody feels safe to drive on the right. Suppose there are only two agents
and
. Then everybody knowing
(formally
) is not enough. Indeed, it might still be possible that the agent
considers possible that the agent
does not know
(formally
). In that case the agent
will not feel safe to drive on the right because he might consider that the agent
, not knowing
, could drive on the left. To avoid this problem, we could then assume that everybody knows that everybody knows that
(formally
). This is again not enough to ensure that everybody feels safe to drive on the right. Indeed, it might still be possible that agent
considers possible that agent
considers possible that agent
does not know
(formally
). In that case and from
’s point of view,
considers possible that
, not knowing
, will drive on the left. So from
’s point of view,
might drive on the left as well (by the same argument as above). So
will not feel safe to drive on the right. Reasoning by induction, Lewis showed that for any
,
Ep\landE1p\land\ldots\landEkp
is not enough for the drivers to feel safe to drive on the right. In fact what we need is an infinite conjunction. In other words, we need common knowledge of
:
.
Distributed knowledge.
Distributed knowledge of
means that if the agents pulled their knowledge altogether, they would know that
holds. In other words, the knowledge of
is
distributed among the agents. The formula
reads as ‘it is distributed knowledge among the set of agents
that
holds’.
Semantics
Epistemic logic is a modal logic. So, what we call an epistemic model
is just a Kripke model as defined in modal logic. The set
is a non-empty set whose elements are called
possible worlds and the
interpretation
is a
function specifying which propositional facts (such as ‘Ann has the red card’) are true in each of these worlds. The
accessibility relations
are
binary relations for each agent
; they are intended to capture the uncertainty of each agent (about the actual world and about the other agents' uncertainty). Intuitively, we have
when the world
is compatible with agent
’s information in world
or, in other words, when agent
considers that world
might correspond to the world
(from this standpoint). We abusively write
for
and
denotes the set of worlds
.
Intuitively, a pointed epistemic model
, where
, represents from an external point of view how the actual world
is perceived by the agents
.
For every epistemic model
, every
and every
}, we define
inductively by the following
truth conditions:
| iff |
|
| iff | rm{it~is~not~the~case~that~}l{M},w\models\phi
|
l{M},w\models\phi\land\psi
| iff | l{M},w\models\phirm{~and~}l{M},w\models\psi
|
| iff | |
| iff | rm{for~all~}v\in\left(\underset{j\in
l{M},v\models\phi
|
| iff | rm{for~all~}v\in\underset{j\inA}{cap}Rj(w),l{M},v\models\phi
| |
where
is the
transitive closure of
: we have that
if, and only if, there are
and
such that
and for all
,
.
Despite the fact that the notion of common belief has to be introduced as a primitive in the language, we can notice that the definition of epistemic models does not have to be modified in order to give truth value to the common knowledge and distributed knowledge operators.
Card Example:
Players
,
and
(standing for Ann, Bob and Claire) play a card game with three cards: a red one, a green one and a blue one. Each of them has a single card but they do not know the cards of the other players. Ann has the red card, Bob has the green card and Claire has the blue card. This example is depicted in the pointed epistemic model
represented below. In this example,
and
PROP:=\{{\color{red}{A}},{\color{green}{B}},{\color{blue}{C}},{\color{red}{B}},{\color{green}{C}},{\color{blue}{A}},{\color{red}{C}},{\color{green}{A}},{\color{blue}{B}}\}
. Each world is labelled by the propositional letters which are true in this world and
corresponds to the actual world. There is an arrow indexed by agent
from a possible world
to a possible world
when
. Reflexive arrows are omitted, which means that for all
and all
, we have that
.
stands for : "
has the red card''
stand for: "
has the blue card''
stands for: "
has the green card''
and so on...
When accessibility relations are equivalence relations (like in this example) and we have that
, we say that agent
cannot distinguish world
from world
(or world
is indistinguishable from world
for agent
). So, for example,
cannot distinguish the actual world
from the possible world where
has the blue card (
),
has the green card (
) and
still has the red card (
).
In particular, the following statements hold:
l{M},w\models({\color{red}{A}}\landKA{\color{red}{A}})\land({\color{blue}{C}}\landKC{\color{blue}{C}})\land({\color{green}{B}}\landKB{\color{green}{B}})
'All the agents know the color of their card'.
l{M},w\modelsKA({\color{blue}{B}}\vee{\color{green}{B}})\landKA({\color{blue}{C}}\vee{\color{green}{C}})
'
knows that
has either the blue or the green card and that
has either the blue or the green card'.
l{M},w\modelsE({\color{red}{A}}\vee{\color{blue}{A}}\vee{\color{green}{A}})\landC({\color{red}{A}}\vee{\color{blue}{A}}\vee{\color{green}{A}})
'Everybody knows that
has either the red, green or blue card and this is even common knowledge among all agents'.
Knowledge versus Belief
We use the same notation
for both knowledge and belief. Hence, depending on the context,
will either read ‘the agent
Knows that
holds’ or ‘the agent
Believes that
holds’. A crucial difference is that, unlike knowledge, beliefs can be
wrong: the axiom
holds only for knowledge, but not necessarily for belief. This axiom called axiom T (for Truth) states that if the agent knows a proposition, then this proposition is true. It is often considered to be the hallmark of knowledge and it has not been subjected to any serious attack ever since its introduction in the
Theaetetus by
Plato.
The notion of knowledge might comply to some other constraints (or axioms) such as
: if agent
knows something, she knows that she knows it. These constraints might affect the nature of the accessibility relations
which may then comply to some extra properties. So, we are now going to define some particular classes of epistemic models that all add some extra constraints on the accessibility relations
. These constraints are matched by particular axioms for the knowledge operator
. Below each property, we give the axiom which
defines[14] the class of epistemic frames that fulfill this property. (
stands for
for any
.)
Properties of accessibility relations and corresponding axiomsserial |
|
D | K\phi → \langleK\rangle\phi
|
transitive | rm{If}~w'\inR(w)~rm{and}~w''\inR(w'),~rm{then}~w''\inR(w)
|
4 |
|
Euclidicity | rm{If}~w'\inR(w)~rm{and}~w''\inR(w),~rm{then}~w'\inR(w'')
|
5 |
|
reflexive |
|
T |
|
symmetric | rm{If}~w'\inR(w),~rm{then}~w\inR(w')
|
B |
|
confluent | rm{If}~w'\inR(w)rm{~and~}w''\inR(w),rm{then~there~is~}vrm{~such~that}~v\inR(w')rm{~and~}v\inR(w'')
|
.2 | \langleK\rangleK\phi → K\langleK\rangle\phi
|
weakly connected | rm{If}~w'\inR(w)rm{~and~}w''\inR(w),rm{~then~}w'=w''rm{~or~}w'\inR(w'')rm{~or~}w''\inR(w')
|
.3 | \langleK\rangle\phi\land\langleK\rangle\psi → \langleK\rangle(\phi\land\psi)\vee\langleK\rangle(\psi\land\langleK\rangle\phi)\vee\langleK\rangle(\phi\land\langleK\rangle\psi)
|
semi-Euclidean | rm{If~}w''\inR(w)rm{~and~}w\notinR(w'')rm{~and~}w'\inR(w),rm{~then~}w''\inR(w')
|
.3.2 | (\langleK\rangle\phi\land\langleK\rangleK\psi) → K(\langleK\rangle\phi\vee\psi)
|
R1 | rm{If~}w''\inR(w)rm{~and~}w ≠ w''rm{~and~}w'\inR(w),rm{~then~}w''\inR(w')
|
.4 | (\phi\land\langleK\rangleK\phi) → K\phi
| |
We discuss the axioms above. Axiom 4 states that if the agent knows a proposition, then she knows that she knows it (this axiom is also known as the “KK-principle”or “KK-thesis”). In epistemology, axiom 4 tends to be accepted by internalists, but not by externalists.[15] Axiom 4 is nevertheless widely accepted by computer scientists (but also by many philosophers, including Plato, Aristotle, Saint Augustine, Spinoza and Schopenhauer, as Hintikka recalls). A more controversial axiom for the logic of knowledge is axiom 5 for Euclidicity: this axiom states that if the agent does not know a proposition, then she knows that she does not know it. Most philosophers (including Hintikka) have attacked this axiom, since numerous examples from everyday life seem to invalidate it.[16] In general, axiom 5 is invalidated when the agent has mistaken beliefs, which can be due for example to misperceptions, lies or other forms of deception. Axiom B states that it cannot be the case that the agent considers it possible that she knows a false proposition (that is,
\neg(\neg\phi\land\negK\negK\phi)
). If we assume that axioms T and 4 are valid, then axiom B falls prey to the same attack as the one for axiom 5 since this axiom is derivable. Axiom D states that the agent's beliefs are consistent. In combination with axiom K (where the knowledge operator is replaced by a belief operator), axiom D is in fact equivalent to a simpler axiom D' which conveys, maybe more explicitly, the fact that the agent's beliefs cannot be inconsistent:
. The other intricate axioms .2, .3, .3.2 and .4 have been introduced by epistemic logicians such as Lenzen and Kutchera in the 1970s and presented for some of them as key axioms of epistemic logic. They can be characterized in terms of intuitive interaction axioms relating knowledge and beliefs.
[17] Axiomatization
The Hilbert proof system K for the basic modal logic is defined by the following axioms and inference rules: for all
,
Proof system
for
Prop | All axioms and inference rules of propositional logic |
K | Kj(\phi → \psi) → (Kj\phi → Kj\psi)
|
Nec | If
then
| |
The axioms of an epistemic logic obviously display the way the agents reason. For example, the axiom K together with the rule of inference Nec entail that if I know
(
) and I know that
implies
(
then I know that
(
). Stronger constraints can be added. The following
proof systems for
} are often used in the literature.
KD45= | K+D+4+5 | | | | S4.2 | = | S4+.2 | | | | S4.3.2 | = | S4+.3.2 | | | | S5 | = | S4+5 |
S4 | = | K+T+4 | | | | S4.3 | = | S4+.3 | | | | S4.4 | = | S4+.4 | | | | Br | = | K+T+B | |
We define the set of proof systems
}:=\.
Moreover, for all
}, we define the proof system
} by adding the following
axiom schemes and
rules of inference to those of
. For all
,
Dis |
|
Mix | CA\phi → EA(\phi\landCA\phi)
|
Ind | rm{if~}\phi → EA(\psi\land\phi)rm{~then~}\phi → CA\psi
| |
The relative strength of the proof systems for knowledge is as follows:
sf{S4}\subsetsf{S4.2}\subsetsf{S4.3}\subsetsf{S4.3.2}\subsetsf{S4.4}\subsetsf{S5}.
So, all the theorems of
are also theorems of
sf{S4.3},sf{S4.3.2},sf{S4.4}
and
. Many philosophers claim that in the most general cases, the logic of knowledge is
or
.
[18] [19] Typically, in computer science and in many of the theories developed in artificial intelligence, the logic of belief (
doxastic logic) is taken to be
and the logic of knowledge (
epistemic logic) is taken to be
, even if
is only suitable for situations where the agents do not have mistaken beliefs.
has been propounded by Floridi as the logic of the notion of 'being informed’ which mainly differs from the logic of knowledge by the absence of introspection for the agents.
[20] For all
}, the
class of
–models or
}–models is the class of epistemic models whose accessibility relations satisfy the properties listed above defined by the axioms of
or
}. Then, for all
},
is
sound and
strongly complete for
} w.r.t. the class of
–models, and
} is
sound and
strongly complete for
}^ w.r.t. the class of
}–models.
Decidability and Complexity
The satisfiability problem for all the logics introduced is decidable. We list below the computational complexity of the satisfiability problem for each of them. Note that it becomes linear in time if there are only finitely many propositional letters in the language. For
, if we restrict to finite nesting, then the satisfiability problem is
NP-complete for all the modal logics considered. If we then further restrict the language to having only finitely many primitive propositions, the complexity goes down to linear in time in all cases.
[21] [22] Complexity of the satisfiability problemLogic |
|
| with common knowledge |
---|
K, S4 | PSPACE | PSPACE | EXPTIME |
KD45 | NP | PSPACE | EXPTIME |
S5 | NP | PSPACE | EXPTIME | |
The computational complexity of the model checking problem is in P in all cases.
Adding Dynamics
Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL) is a logical framework for modeling epistemic situations involving several agents, and changes that occur to these situations as a result of incoming information or more generally incoming action. The methodology of DEL is such that it splits the task of representing the agents’ beliefs and knowledge into three parts:
- One represents their beliefs about an initial situation thanks to an epistemic model;
- One represents their beliefs about an event taking place in this situation thanks to an event model;
- One represents the way the agents update their beliefs about the situation after (or during) the occurrence of the event thanks to a product update.
Typically, an informative event can be a public announcement to all the agents of a formula
: this public announcement and correlative update constitute the dynamic part. However, epistemic events can be much more complex than simple public announcement, including hiding information for some of the agents, cheating, lying, bluffing,
etc. This complexity is dealt with when we introduce the notion of event model. We will first focus on public announcements to get an intuition of the main underlying ideas of DEL.
Public Events
In this section, we assume that all events are public. We start by giving a concrete example where DEL can be used, to better understand what is going on. This example is called the muddy children puzzle. Then, we will present a formalization of this puzzle in a logic called Public Announcement Logic (PAL). The muddy children puzzle is one of the most well known puzzles that played a role in the development of DEL. Other significant puzzles include the sum and product puzzle, the Monty Hall dilemma, the Russian cards problem, the two envelopes problem, Moore's paradox, the hangman paradox, etc.[23]
Muddy Children Example:
We have two children, A and B, both dirty. A can see B but not himself, and B can see A but not herself. Let
be the proposition stating that A is dirty, and
be the proposition stating that B is dirty.
- We represent the initial situation by the pointed epistemic model
represented below, where relations between worlds are equivalence relations. States
intuitively represent possible worlds, a proposition (for example
) satisfiable at one of these worlds intuitively means that in the corresponding possible world, the intuitive interpretation of
(A is dirty) is true. The links between worlds labelled by agents (A or B) intuitively express a notion of indistinguishability for the agent at stake between two possible worlds. For example, the link between
and
labelled by A intuitively means that A can not distinguish the possible world
from
and vice versa. Indeed, A cannot see himself, so he cannot distinguish between a world where he is dirty and one where he is not dirty. However, he can distinguish between worlds where B is dirty or not because he can see B. With this intuitive interpretation we are brought to assume that our relations between worlds are equivalence relations.
- Now, suppose that their father comes and announces that at least one is dirty (formally,
). Then we update the model and this yields the pointed epistemic model represented below. What we actually do is suppressing the worlds where the content of the announcement is not fulfilled. In our case this is the world where
and
are true. This suppression is what we call the update. We then get the model depicted below. As a result of the announcement, both A and B do know that at least one of them is dirty. We can read this from the epistemic model.
- Now suppose there is a second (and final) announcement that says that neither knows they are dirty (an announcement can express facts about the situation as well as epistemic facts about the knowledge held by the agents). We then update similarly the model by suppressing the worlds which do not satisfy the content of the announcement, or equivalently by keeping the worlds which do satisfy the announcement. This update process thus yields the pointed epistemic model represented below. By interpreting this model, we get that A and B both know that they are dirty, which seems to contradict the content of the announcement. However, if we assume that A and B are both perfect reasoners and that this is common knowledge among them, then this inference makes perfect sense.
Public announcement logic (PAL):
We present the syntax and semantic of Public Announcement Logic (PAL), which combines features of epistemic logic and propositional dynamic logic.[24]
We define the language
}
inductively by the following grammar in BNF:
}:\phi~~::=~~ p~\mid~\neg\phi~\mid~(\phi\land\phi)~\mid~K_j\phi~\mid~[\phi!]\phi
where
.
The language
}
is interpreted over epistemic models. The truth conditions for the connectives of the epistemic language are the same as in epistemic logic (see above). The truth condition for the new dynamic action modality
is defined as follows:
| iff | ifl{M},w\models\psithenl{M}\psi,w\models\phi
| |
where
withW\psi:=\{w\inW;l{M},w\models\psi\}
,
for all
and
I\psi(w):=I(w)rm{~for~all~}w\inW\psi
.
The formula
intuitively means that after a truthful announcement of
,
holds. A public announcement of a proposition
changes the current epistemic model like in the figure below.
The proof system
defined below is sound and strongly complete for
} w.r.t. the class of all pointed epistemic models.
| | The Axioms and the rules of inference of the proof system
(see above) |
Red 1 | | [\psi!]p\leftrightarrow(\psi → p)
|
Red 2 | | [\psi!]\neg\phi\leftrightarrow(\psi → \neg[\psi!]\phi)
|
Red 3 | | [\psi!](\phi\land\chi)\leftrightarrow([\psi!]\phi\land[\psi!]\chi)
|
Red 4 | | [\psi!]Ki\phi\leftrightarrow\left(\psi → Ki(\psi → [\psi!]\phi)\right)
| |
The axioms Red 1 - Red 4 are called reduction axioms because they allow to reduce any formula of
}
to a provably equivalent formula of
in
. The formula
is a theorem provable in
. It states that after a public announcement of
, the agent knows that
holds.PAL is decidable, its model checking problem is solvable in polynomial time and its satisfiability problem is PSPACE-complete.[25]
Muddy children puzzle formalized with PAL:
Here are some of the statements that hold in the muddy children puzzle formalized in PAL.
'In the initial situation, A is dirty and B is dirty'.
l{N},s\models(\negKAp\land\negKA\negp)\land(\negKBq\land\negKB\negq)
'In the initial situation, A does not know whether he is dirty and B neither'.
l{N},s\models[p\veeq!](KA(p\veeq)\landKB(p\veeq))
'After the public announcement that at least one of the children A and B is dirty, both of them know that at least one of them is dirty'. However:
l{N},s\models[p\veeq!]((\negKAp\land\negKA\negp)\land(\negKBq\land\negKB\negq))
'After the public announcement that at least one of the children A and B is dirty, they still do not know that they are dirty'. Moreover:
l{N},s\models[p\veeq!][(\negKAp\land\negKA\negp)\land(\negKBq\land\negKB\negq)!](KAp\landKBq)
'After the successive public announcements that at least one of the children A and B is dirty and that they still do not know whether they are dirty, A and B then both know that they are dirty'.
In this last statement, we see at work an interesting feature of the update process: a formula is not necessarily true after being announced. That is what we technically call “self-persistence” and this problem arises for epistemic formulas (unlike propositional formulas). One must not confuse the announcement and the update induced by this announcement, which might cancel some of the information encoded in the announcement.[26]
Arbitrary Events
In this section, we assume that events are not necessarily public and we focus on items 2 and 3 above, namely on how to represent events and on how to update an epistemic model with such a representation of events by means of a product update.
Event Model
Epistemic models are used to model how agents perceive the actual world. Their perception can also be described in terms of knowledge and beliefs about the world and about the other agents’ beliefs. The insight of the DEL approach is that one can describe how an event is perceived by the agents in a very similar way. Indeed, the agents’ perception of an event can also be described in terms of knowledge and beliefs. For example, the private announcement of
to
that her card is red can also be described in terms of knowledge and beliefs: while
tells
that her card is red (event
)
believes that nothing happens (event
). This leads to define the notion of event model whose definition is very similar to that of an epistemic model.
A pointed event model
represents how the actual event represented by
is perceived by the agents. Intuitively,
means that while the possible event represented by
is occurring, agent
considers possible that the possible event represented by
is actually occurring.
An event model is a tuple
where:
is a non-empty set of
possible events,
\subseteqW\alpha x W\alpha
is a binary relation called an
accessibility relation on
, for each
,
I\alpha:W\alpha → l{L}sf{EL
} is a function called the
precondition function assigning to each possible event a formula of
}.
denotes the set
\{f\inW\alpha;(e,f)\in
\}
.We write
for
, and
is called a
pointed event model (
often represents the actual event).
Card Example:
Let us resume the card example and assume that players
and
show their card to each other. As it turns out,
noticed that
showed her card to
but did not notice that
did so to
. Players
and
know this. This event is represented below in the event model
.
The possible event
corresponds to the actual event ‘players
and
show their and cards respectively to each other’ (with precondition
{\color{red}{A}}\land{\color{green}{B}}
),
stands for the event ‘player
shows her green card’ (with precondition
) and
stands for the atomic event ‘player
shows her red card’ (with precondition
). Players
and
show their cards to each other, players
and
know this and consider it possible, while player
considers possible that player
shows her red card and also considers possible that player
shows her green card, since he does not know her card. In fact, that is all that player
considers possible because she did not notice that
showed her card.
Another example of event model is given below. This second example corresponds to the event whereby Player
shows her red card publicly to everybody. Player
shows her red card, players
,
and
‘know’ it, players
,
and
‘know’ that each of them ‘knows’ it,
etc. In other words, there is
common knowledge among players
,
and
that player
shows her red card.
Product Update
The DEL product update is defined below.[27] This update yields a new pointed epistemic model
representing how the new situation which was previously represented by
is perceived by the agents after the occurrence of the event represented by
.
Let
be an epistemic model and let
be an event model. The
product update of
and
is the epistemic model
defined as follows: for all
and all
,
| = | \{(v,f)\inW x W\alpha;l{M},v\modelsI\alpha(f)\}
|
| = |
|
| = |
| |
If
and
are such that
then
denotes the pointed epistemic model
. This definition of the product update is conceptually grounded.
Card Example:
As a result of the first event described above (Players
and
show their cards to each other in front of player
), the agents update their beliefs. We get the situation represented in the pointed epistemic model
below. In this pointed epistemic model, the following statement holds:
(l{M},w) ⊗ (l{E},e)\models({\color{green}{B}}\landKA{\color{green}{B}})\landKC\negKA{\color{green}{B}}.
It states that player
knows that player
has the card but player
'believes' that it is not the case.
The result of the second event is represented below. In this pointed epistemic model, the following statement holds:
(l{M},w) ⊗ (l{F},e)\modelsC\{B,C\
}(\land\land)\land \neg K_A(\land). It states that there is common knowledge among
and
that they know the true state of the world (namely
has the red card,
has the green card and
has the blue card), but
does not know it.
Based on these three components (epistemic model, event model and product update), Baltag, Moss and Solecki defined a general logical language inspired from the logical language of propositional dynamic logic to reason about information and knowledge change.
See also
References
- Book: Johan. van Benthem. Logical Dynamics of Information and Interaction. Cambridge University Press. 2011. 978-0521873970.
- Book: van Ditmarsch. Hans. Joseph. Halpern. Wiebe. van der Hoek. Barteld. Kooi. Handbook of Epistemic Logic. London. College publication. 2015. 978-1848901582.
- Book: van Ditmarsch, Hans, van der Hoek, Wiebe, and Kooi, Barteld. Dynamic Epistemic Logic. Ithaca. volume 337 of Synthese library. Springer.. 2007. 978-1-4020-5839-4.
- Book: Ronald. Fagin. Joseph. Halpern. Yoram. Moses. Moshe. Vardi. Reasoning about Knowledge. Cambridge. MIT Press. 2003. 978-0-262-56200-3. A classic reference.
- Book: Jaakko. Hintikka. Knowledge and Belief - An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. registration. Ithaca. Cornell University Press. 1962. 978-1-904987-08-6. .
External links
- dynamic-epistemic . Dynamic Epistemic Logic . Baltag. Alexandru. Renne. Bryan.
- de-logic . Dynamic Epistemic Logic. van Ditmarsch. Hans. van der Hoek. Wiebe. Kooi. Barteld.
- logic-epistemic . Epistemic Logic . Hendricks. Vincent. Symons. John.
- logic-modal . Modal logic . Garson . James.
Notes and References
- Logics of public communications. Synthese. 2007-07-26. 0039-7857. 165–179. 158. 2. 10.1007/s11229-007-9168-7. Jan. Plaza. 41619205 .
- Reasoning about Information Change. Journal of Logic, Language and Information. 1997-04-01. 0925-8531. 147–169. 6. 2. 10.1023/A:1008222603071. Jelle. Gerbrandy. Willem. Groeneveld. 1700635 .
- Defaults in update semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic. 1996-06-01. 0022-3611. 221–261. 25. 3. 10.1007/BF00248150. Frank. Veltman. 10.1.1.77.9349. 19377671 .
- Descriptions of Game Actions. Journal of Logic, Language and Information. 2002-06-01. 0925-8531. 349–365. 11. 3. 10.1023/A:1015590229647. Hans P. van. Ditmarsch. 195220171 .
- Logics for Epistemic Programs. Synthese. 2004-03-01. 0039-7857. 165–224. 139. 2. 10.1023/B:SYNT.0000024912.56773.5e. Alexandru. Baltag. Lawrence S.. Moss. 18793176 .
- A distinction is sometimes made between events and actions, an action being a specific type of event performed by an agent.
- Book: Boh, Ivan. Epistemic Logic in the later Middle Ages. Routledge. 1993. 978-0415057264.
- Book: Jaako, Hintikka. Knowledge and Belief, An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. Cornell University Press. 1962. 978-1904987086. Ithaca and London.
- Recent Work in Epistemic Logic. Lenzen. Wolfgang. 1978. Acta Philosophica Fennica.
- Recent results on belief, knowledge and the epistemic foundations of game theory. Research in Economics. 1999-06-01. 149–225. 53. 2. 10.1006/reec.1999.0187. Pierpaolo. Battigalli. Giacomo. Bonanno. 10419/189483.
- Book: Reasoning about Knowledge. Ronald Fagin . Joseph Halpern . Yoram Moses . Moshe Vardi . MIT Press. 1995. 9780262562003.
- Book: Lewis, David. Convention, a Philosophical Study. Harvard University Press. 1969. 978-0674170254.
- Agreeing to Disagree. 2958591. The Annals of Statistics. 1976-11-01. 1236–1239. 4. 6. Robert J.. Aumann. 10.1214/aos/1176343654. free.
- Book: Modal Logic. Patrick Blackburn . Maarten de Rijke . Yde Venema . Cambridge University Press. 2001. 978-0521527149.
- Web site: Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy » KK Principle (Knowing that One Knows) Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy » Print. www.iep.utm.edu. 2015-12-11. https://web.archive.org/web/20160304205052/http://www.iep.utm.edu/kk-princ/print/. 2016-03-04. dead.
- For example, assume that a university professor believes (is certain) that one of her colleague’s seminars is on Thursday (formally
). She is actually wrong because it is on Tuesday (
). Therefore, she does not know that her colleague’s seminar is on Tuesday (
). If we assume that axiom is valid then we should conclude that she knows that she does not know that her colleague’s seminar is on Tuesday (
) (and therefore she also believes that she does not know it:
). This is obviously counterintuitive.
- Intricate Axioms as Interaction Axioms. Studia Logica. 2015-03-18. 0039-3215. 1035–1062. 103. 5. 10.1007/s11225-015-9609-0. Guillaume. Aucher. 255074436 .
- Epistemologische betrachtungen zu [S4, S5]. Erkenntnis. 1979-03-01. 0165-0106. 33–56. 14. 1. 10.1007/BF00205012. de. Wolfgang. Lenzen. 122982410 .
- On Logics of Knowledge and Belief. Philosophical Studies. 2006-03-01. 0031-8116. 169–199. 128. 1. 10.1007/s11098-005-4062-y. Robert. Stalnaker. 170320855 .
- Book: Floridi, Luciano. http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199232383.001.0001/acprof-9780199232383-chapter-10. 224–243. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199232383.003.0010. 9780191594809. Oxford University Press. 2011-01-27. The Philosophy of Information. The logic of being informed.
- A guide to completeness and complexity for modal logics of knowledge and belief. Artificial Intelligence. 319–379. 54. 3. 10.1016/0004-3702(92)90049-4. Joseph Y.. Halpern. Yoram. Moses. 1992.
- The effect of bounding the number of primitive propositions and the depth of nesting on the complexity of modal logic. Artificial Intelligence. 1995-06-01. 361–372. 75. 2. 10.1016/0004-3702(95)00018-A. Joseph Y.. Halpern. free.
- Book: One Hundred Prisoners and a Light Bulb - Springer . 10.1007/978-3-319-16694-0 . Hans . van Ditmarsch . Barteld . Kooi. 2015 . 978-3-319-16693-3 .
- Book: Dynamic Logic. David Harel. Dexter Kozen. Jerzy Tiuryn. MIT Press. 2000. 978-0262082891. registration.
- Book: Lutz, Carsten. ACM. 2006-01-01. New York, NY, USA. 978-1-59593-303-4. 137–143. AAMAS '06. 10.1145/1160633.1160657. Proceedings of the fifth international joint conference on Autonomous agents and multiagent systems . Complexity and succinctness of public announcement logic . 1083518 .
- The Secret of My Success. Synthese. 2006-07-01. 0039-7857. 201–232. 151. 2. 10.1007/s11229-005-3384-9. Hans Van. Ditmarsch. Barteld. Kooi. 39421146 .
- The Logic of Public Announcements and Common Knowledge and Private Suspicions. Alexandru Baltag . Lawrence S. Moss . Slawomir Solecki . 1998. Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge (TARK).