Divine simplicity explained

In classical theistic and monotheistic theology, the doctrine of divine simplicity says that God is simple (without parts).God exists as one unified entity, with no distinct attributes; God’s existence is identical to God’s essence.

Overview

The being of God is identical to the "attributes" of God. Characteristics such as omnipresence, goodness, truth and eternity are identical to God's being, not qualities that make up that being as a collection or abstract entities inherent to God as in a substance; in God, essence and existence are the same.[1]

Simplicity denies any physical or metaphysical composition in the divine being. God is the divine nature itself, with no accidents (unnecessary properties) accruing to his nature. There are no real divisions or distinctions of this nature; the entirety of God is whatever is attributed to him. God does not have goodness, but is goodness; God does not existence, but is existence. According to Thomas Aquinas, God is God's existence and God's essence is God's existence.[2] Divine simplicity is the hallmark of God’s transcendence of all else, ensuring that the divine nature is beyond the reach of ordinary categories and distinctions (or, at least, their ordinary application). "Simplicity in this way confers a unique ontological status that many philosophers find highly peculiar."[3] When it comes to God's essential nature or attributes, there are no parts or accidents; this is not to be confused with God's accidental or contingent relation to the world (God's non-essential or contingent properties, not God's nature).[4]

Varieties of this doctrine exist among Jewish, Christian, and Muslim philosophical theologians, especially during the height of scholasticism. Its origins may be traced back to ancient Greek thought, finding apotheosis in Plotinus' Enneads as the Simplex.[6] [7] [8]

History

Views similar to divine simplicity were held by philosophers such as Plato, Thales and Anaximenes. Classical statements about divine simplicity can be found in Augustine, Anselm and Thomas Aquinas. In early Christianity, Philo of Alexandria said that the belief of God as utterly simple was widely held.[9] One of the earliest mentions of divine simplicity in Christian theology is by Irenaeus (130).[10] Early Christian theology viewed simplicity as necessary for preserving God's transcendence; Athenagoras of Athens, in the second century, said that God is indivisible and unchangeable.[11] }}

According to Maimonides, there can be no plurality of faculties, moral dispositions, or essential attributes in God. To say that God is all-knowing, all-powerful, and all-good is to introduce plurality, if these qualities are separate attributes. Maimonides concluded that it is untrue to say that God's power is greater than ours, that God's life is more permanent than ours, or God's knowledge is broader than ours. He believed that statements such as "God lives" or "God is powerful" are nonsense if they are interpreted normally, but they can be understood if analyzed as disguised negations. Maimonedes also believed that negation is objectionable to the degree that it introduces complexity; God is neither this nor that, and verbal expression fails us. Citing Psalm 65, he concluded that the highest form of praise of God is silence.[12]

For others, the axiom of divine unity (Shema) forms the understanding of divine simplicity. Bahya ibn Paquda (Duties of the Heart 1:8) points out that God's oneness is "true oneness" (האחד האמת), as opposed to "circumstantial oneness" (האחד המקרי). He develops this idea to show that an entity that is truly one must be free of properties, indescribable, and unlike anything else. Such an entity would not be subject to change, utterly independent, and the root of everything.[13]

The implication of either approach is so strong that the two concepts are often presented as synonymous: "God is not two or more entities, but a single entity of oneness even more single and unique than any single thing in creation ... He cannot be sub-divided into different partstherefore, He can't be anything other than one. It is a positive commandment to know this, for it is written (Deuteronomy 6:4) ' ... the Lord is our God, the Lord is one.[14]

Despite its apparent simplicity, this concept raises a number of difficulties. Since God's simplicity does not allow for any structureeven conceptuallydivine simplicity appears to entail the following dichotomy:

This paradox is articulated by Moshe Chaim Luzzatto in Derech Hashem, who describes the dichotomy as arising from the inability to comprehend absolute unity:

Christian thought

See also: Trinity and Nontrinitarianism. Simplicity (or metaphysical, absolute simplicity) states that the characteristics of God are not parts of God which make up God. God is simple; God is those characteristics. God does not have goodness, but is goodness; God does not existence, but existence. According to Thomas Aquinas, God is God's existence and God's essence is God's existence.[15] God is goodness, which is his nature, which is his essence, which is his existence.[16] William F. Vallicella says, "To say that God lacks metaphysical parts is to say inter alia that God is free of matter-form composition, potency-act composition, and existence-essence composition. There is also no real distinction between God as a subject of his attributes and his attributes."[17] God exhausts what it means to be God and, in principle, there cannot be more than one God.[18] [21] According to Duns Scotus, there is a formal distinction between God's attributes.[18] [21] This distinction is not conceptual or metaphysical.[18] [21] The formal distinction is logical; omnipotence is not logically equivalent to omniscience.[18] [21] Duns Scotus affirms that God's nature is not composed of metaphysical properties or parts.[18] [21] [22]

Yann Schmitt says,

The notion of de re is contrasted with de dicto. De dicto concerns a proposition about what is said, and de re concerns the thing (or being).[23] A formal distinction exists between the attribute of omnipotence and the attribute of omniscience because omnipotence and omniscience are inseparable for an omnipotent being (God); omnipotence and omniscience do not have the same definition, and the distinction between them exists de re (not conceptually or propositionallyde dicto).[23] A formal distinction is a logical distinction.[22] The upshot for Scotus is that omnipotence and omniscience are logically distinct for God, who does not have the metaphysical properties (or attributes) of omnipotence or omniscience;[22] metaphysically speaking, God omnipotence and omniscient.[22]

Spatial simplicity is endorsed by most traditional Christian theists, who do not consider God a physical object. Temporal simplicity is endorsed by many theists, but is controversial among Christian theologians. Thomas V. Morris controversially describes property simplicity as the property of having no properties.[24]

In the medieval era, theologians and philosophers held a view known as "constituent ontology" wherein natures were constituents of things. According to Aquinas, an individual nature was more like a concrete object than an abstract object. One person's humanity was not the same as another person's humanity; each had human nature, individuated by the matter (materia signata) from which each person was composed. For entities which are immaterial (such as angels), there is no matter to individuate their nature; each one is its nature. Each angel is one of a kind, although this claim was controversial.[25]

Theologians holding the doctrine of property simplicity distinguish modes of divine simplicity by negating any notion of composition from the meaning of terms used to describe it. In quantitative or spatial terms, God is simpleas opposed to being made up of piecesand present in entirety everywhere if, in fact, present anywhere. In terms of essence, God is simple as opposed to being made up of form and matter, body and soul, or mind and act. If distinctions are made between God's attributes, they are distinctions of the "modes" of God's being rather than real or essential divisions. In terms of subjects and accidents (as in the phrase "goodness of God"), divine simplicity allows for a conceptual distinction between the person of God and the personal attribute of goodness but disallows that God's identity (or "character") is dependent on goodness. According to the doctrine, it is impossible to consider the goodness in which God participates separately from the goodness which God is.[26]

Aquinas says that as creatures, our concepts are drawn from the creation (the assumption of empiricism); according to divine simplicity, God's attributes can only be spoken of by analogy since the properties of any created thing differ from its being.[27] Divine simplicity was dogmatized in the Catholic Church at the Fourth Lateran Council and First Vatican Council, and is accepted in some form by most Christians.[28]

Criticism

Absolute (Thomistic) divine simplicity has been criticized by a number of Christian theologians, including John S. Feinberg, Thomas Morris, William Lane Craig, and Alvin Plantinga; in his essay Does God Have a Nature?, Plantinga calls it "a dark saying indeed."[29] Plantinga presents three arguments against Thomistic divine simplicity. Concepts can apply univocally to God, even if language to describe God is limited, fragmentary, halting, and inchoate.[30] In the concept of something like being a horse, for something to be a horse is known; the concept applies to an object if the object is a horse. If no concepts apply to God, it is confusing to say that there is such a person as God; God does not have properties such as wisdom, creation and omnipotence, and would not have any properties for which there are concepts. God would not have properties such as existence or self-identification. If God transcends human experience, nothing can be said univocally about God; such a claim presupposes knowledge, transcending human experience, which applies to God. One reply to this objection is to distinguish equivocal language and analogical language; the former lacks a univocal element, but the latter has an element of univocal language.[31]

The claim that God can only be described analogically is, according to Plantinga, a double-edged sword. If univocal language cannot be used to describe God and argue against simplicity, it cannot be used in arguments for Thomistic divine simplicity. If the usual modes of inference in reasoning about God cannot be used, it cannot be argued that God is not distinct from his properties. Plantinga concludes, "This way of thinking begins in a pious and commendable concern for God's greatness and majesty and augustness, but it ends in agnosticism and in incoherence."[32] Edward Feser has responded to Plantinga.[33] Feser says that Plantinga is attacking a strawman when he says that proponents of analogical (religious) language are committed to the view that the language of God is metaphorical and not literal; metaphorical language differs from analogical language, so Plantinga is conflating analogy with metaphor.[33]

Plantinga presents three criticisms of metaphysical simplicity, saying that it is difficult to grasp the doctrine and difficult to see why anyone would accept it. According to the Thomist doctrine of simplicity states, all abstract objects are identical with God's essence and, hence, God himself. Plantinga says that this clashes with the fact that the property of being a horse is distinct from the property of being a turkey, and both are distinct from God and his essence.[34] One response to this objection is to note a distinction between properties and predicates.[31] A second response notes that supporters of divine simplicity do not think of God's nature as exemplifying abstract objects that are independent of God.[33]

Plantinga says that if abstract objects that are identical with God are restricted to the properties God exemplifies, the doctrine remains problematic. Metaphysical simplicity states that God has no accidental (contingent) properties, it seems that God has accidental properties such as having created Adam and knowing that Adam sinned. Some of God's characteristics characterize him in every possible world, and others do not.[35] Plantinga also says that the conflation of God's actuality with his potentiality is problematic. As it seems that there are characteristics God has but could have lacked, it also seems that God lacks characteristics he could have had. God has not created all the persons he will create; there is at least one individual essence that God does not now have, but will have. If so, God has potentiality with respect to that characteristic.[36] Feser notes that someone who holds to divine simplicity does not have to hold to this view; one can think that God has "Cambridge" properties, which are properties in a loose sense (such as the "property" of being a husband or creating a universe).[33]

Plantinga's third critique challenges the heart of simplicity. Metaphysical simplicity claims that there is no divine composition; there is no complexity of properties in God, and he is identical with his nature and each of his properties. According to Plantinga, this view has two difficulties. If God is identical with each of his properties, each of his properties is identical with each of his other properties; God has only one property. This flies in the face of the idea that God has power and mercy, neither of which is identical with the other. If God is identical with his properties and each of God's properties is a property, God is a property and has one property: himself. However, properties do not cause anything; no property could have created the world, and no property could know anything. If God is a property, he is an abstract object with no power, life, love, or awareness.[37] Feser notes that this objection assumes a Platonist metaphysics about abstract objects. Supporters of divine simplicity do not think of God as a Platonic-abstract property or impersonal; God is personal, personhood, and intelligent.[38] Vallicella responds to Plantinga by arguing that Plantinga's objections assume a non-constituent ontology and are unconvincing.[17] In his 1983 review of Does God Have a Nature?, Alfred J. Freddoso wrote that Plantinga's critique lacks the depth of analysis to propose jettisoning the theological basis of divine simplicity laid in Christian thought by Augustine, Anselm, Bonaventure, Aquinas, Scotus, Ockham, and others.[40]

William Lane Craig calls the Thomistic view of property simplicity "philosophically and theologically unacceptable", also objecting to divine simplicity. According to the doctrine, God is similar in all possible worlds. Since the statement "God knows x" is equivalent to "x is true," it is inexplicable why those worlds vary if, in every one, God knows, loves, and wills the same things.[25] Feser responded to Craig's objections to divine simplicity.[41] [42] [43] Morris calls it is an idea whose implications are difficult to defend, and whose advantages can be had in other ways. It is an idea whose motivation, under close scrutiny, unconvincing.[44] John S. Feinberg writes, "These philosophical problems plus the biblical considerations raised earlier lead me to conclude that simplicity is not one of the divine attributes. This doesn't mean that God has physical parts, but that the implications of the doctrine of metaphysical simplicity are too problematic to maintain the doctrine."[45] Jordan Barrett responded to the claim that divine simplicity is not biblical.[46]

Jeffrey Brower and Michael Bergmann present a truthmaker defense of divine simplicity.[26] Saying "God is omnibenevolent" means that "God is his omnibenevolence"; God is not identical to a property of omnibenevolence; he is identical to God's goodness, and identical to himself.[47] [26] Vallicella says, "Accordingly, to say that God is identical to his omniscience is just to say that God is identical to the truthmaker of 'God is omniscient'. And that amounts to saying that God is identical to God. In this way, one avoids the absurdity of saying that God is identical to a property. What God is identical to is not the property of omniscience but the referent of ‘God’s omniscience,’ which turns out to be God himself. And similarly for the rest of God’s intrinsic and essential attributes."[48] Another truthmaker theory posits a moderate version of divine simplicity between absolute divine simplicity (God is not composed of metaphysical parts) and minimal divine simplicity (God is not composed of spatial, temporal or material parts). The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity. According to this view, God would not be composed but would be complex. Yann says, "The minimal truthmaker requirement can then be assumed without any contradiction with divine simplicity. is true in virtue of the perfection of God, that is God’s goodness. is true in virtue of another perfection of God, God’s omniscience. We do not have to say that God is identical with His goodness or His omniscience."[49]

Scriptural arguments

Writers such as Herman Bavinck and Louis Berkhof have argued that the doctrine of divine simplicity is affirmed by the Epistle of John, since its author seems to identify God with love[50] and light.[51] Advocates of the doctrine have also argued that it is affirmed by Old Testament passages such as Exodus 3:14 (identifying God as "being"), Deuteronomy 6:4 (seen as affirming the oneness of God) and Jeremiah 23:6, identifying God with righteousness. Critics of the doctrine say that it is unlikely that the biblical authors had metaphysics in mind in the verses used, and the lack of explicit verses on the doctrine argues against it.[52] Theologians such as Charles Caldwell Ryrie have argued that divine simplicity underscores the scriptural view of God's self-existence.[53]

Islamic thought

See also: Attributes of God in Islam. Views of divine simplicity were championed by the Mu'tazili, which resulted in an apophatic theology. By postulating a distinction between existence and essence for all created beings, which was perceived to be uniquely absent in God, Al-Farabi established another model of divine simplicity. Ibn Sinā supported and elaborated this position; Al-Ghazali contested this identification of divine essence and existence, but saw divine attributes and acts as enveloped in (and indistinct from) the divine essence. This view of divine simplicity was shared with critics of Muslim philosophical writers such as Ibn Taymiyyah.[54]

See also

Bibliography

External links

Notes and References

  1. Web site: Summa Theologiae: The simplicity of God (Prima Pars, Q. 3). newadvent.com. 2019-10-09.
  2. Web site: Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  3. Web site: Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  4. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/divine-simplicity/#GodMcCaDDSConcStatAffa . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Divine Simplicity . 2019 . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University .
  5. [4]
  6. Bussanich John, Plotinus's metaphysics of the One in The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, ed. Lloyd P.Gerson, p. 42, 1996, Cambridge University Press, UK. For instances, see Plotinus, Second Ennead, Fourth Tractate, Section 8 (Stephen MacKenna's translation, Sacred Texts)
  7. Web site: The Enneads of Plotinus: The Fifth Ennead: Fourth Tractate: Section 1. www.sacred-texts.com.
  8. Web site: The Enneads of Plotinus: The Second Ennead: Ninth Tractate: Section 1. www.sacred-texts.com.
  9. Web site: Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy . 2022-05-28 . en-US.
  10. Book: Simons, Jonatán . Divine Simplicity in the Theology of Irenaeus . 2023-09-28 . Brill . 978-90-04-67763-0 . en.
  11. [Clement of Alexandria]
  12. Seeskin. Kenneth. Maimonedes. 22 April 2014. 2006-01-24. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archive.
  13. https://web.archive.org/web/20050318170731/http://www.torah.org/learning/spiritual-excellence/classes/doh-1-8.html Torah.org – The Judaism Site
  14. Web site: Maimonides. Mishneh Torah. yes. Mada 1:7. https://web.archive.org/web/20230716051616/https://www.panix.com/~jjbaker/MadaYHT.html. 16 July 2023. live.
  15. Web site: Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  16. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/divine-simplicity/#IdenDiviAttr . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Divine Simplicity . 2019 . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University .
  17. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/divine-simplicity/#GodHisNatu . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Divine Simplicity . 2019 . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University .
  18. Web site: Scotus, John Duns | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  19. John Duns Scotus has a more moderate view of metaphysical simplicity than Aquinas.[18]

  20. Divine simplicity is fundamentally about God's attributes: his nature or essence. The doctrine does not state that God cannot have the "property" of creating a universe.[18]
  21. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/duns-scotus/#DivInfDocUni . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . John Duns Scotus . 2019 . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University .
  22. Web site: Scotus, John Duns | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  23. Web site: De re/De dicto – Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  24. Book: Morris, Thomas V.. Our idea of God : an introduction to philosophical theology. 1997. Regent College Pub. . 114. Vancouver, B.C.. 978-1573831017.
  25. Web site: Craig. William Lane. Divine Simplicity. 22 April 2014.
  26. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/divine-simplicity/#TrutDefe . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Divine Simplicity . 2019 . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University .
  27. White . Thomas Joseph . Divine Simplicity . St Andrews Encyclopaedia of Theology . 2022.
  28. Web site: Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  29. Plantinga, Alvin. "Does God Have a Nature?" in Plantinga, Alvin, and James F. Sennett. 1998. The analytic theist: an Alvin Plantinga reader. Grand Rapids, Michigan: W. B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 228.
  30. Book: Plantinga, Alvin. Does God have a nature?. 2000. Marquette Univ. Press. Milwaukee. 978-0874621457. Reprinted. 18.
  31. Web site: Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  32. Book: Plantinga, Alvin. Does God have a nature?. 2000. Marquette Univ. Press. Milwaukee. 978-0874621457. Reprinted. 26.
  33. Edward Feser. Five Proofs of the Existence of God. San Francisco, California:Ignatius Press, 2017
  34. Book: Plantinga, Alvin. Does God have a nature?. 2000. Marquette Univ. Press. Milwaukee. 978-0874621457. Reprinted. 37.
  35. Book: Plantinga, Alvin. Does God have a nature?. 2000. Marquette Univ. Press. Milwaukee. 978-0874621457. Reprinted. 43.
  36. Book: Plantinga, Alvin. Does God have a nature?. 2000. Marquette Univ. Press. Milwaukee. 978-0874621457. Reprinted. 46.
  37. Book: Plantinga, Alvin. Does God have a nature?. 2000. Marquette Univ. Press. Milwaukee. 978-0874621457. Reprinted. 47.
  38. Book: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/divine-simplicity/#PropOneSamePredNoGuarSameProp . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Divine Simplicity . 2019 . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University .
  39. God does not only have the concrete property of divine simplicity; for God, God is God's essential "properties" (attributes). A distinction exists between properties and predicates, so humans distinguish power from mercy; in divine simplicity, power and mercy are the same things in God.[38]
  40. Freddoso A . Review of Does God Have a Nature? . Christian Scholar's Review . 78–83 . 1983 . 12 . 2 . University of Notre Dame .
  41. Web site: Keep It Simple | Edward Feser . April 2020 .
  42. Web site: Edward Feser: William Lane Craig on divine simplicity . November 2009 .
  43. Web site: Edward Feser: Craig on divine simplicity and theistic personalism . 15 April 2016 .
  44. Book: Morris, Thomas V.. Our idea of God : an introduction to philosophical theology. 1997. Regent College Pub. . 115. Vancouver, B.C.. 978-1573831017.
  45. Book: John S. Feinberg . No One Like Him: the doctrine of God. 2006. Crossway Books. Wheaton. Ill.. 978-1581348118. 335. Revised.
  46. Barrett, J. P. (2017). Divine Simplicity: A Biblical and Trinitarian Account. United Kingdom: Fortress Press.
  47. Bergmann, Michael, and Jeffrey Brower. “A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)” In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 2, edited by Dean Zimmerman, 357–386. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
  48. Vallicella, William F., "Divine Simplicity", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
  49. Schmitt, Yann (2013). The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 (1):117–130.
  50. 1 John 4:8
  51. 1 John 1:5
  52. Book: Dolezal, James E. . God Without Parts . 2011-11-09 . Wipf & Stock Publishers . 978-1-4982-6155-5 . en.
  53. Book: Ryrie, Charles C. . Basic Theology: A Popular Systematic Guide to Understanding Biblical Truth . 1999-01-11 . Moody Publishers . 978-1-57567-498-8 . en.
  54. Book: Arberry, A.J. . Revelation and Reason in Islam . Routledge . New York . 104–108 . 2007 . 978-0415438872.