In mathematics, linear maps form an important class of "simple" functions which preserve the algebraic structure of linear spaces and are often used as approximations to more general functions (see linear approximation). If the spaces involved are also topological spaces (that is, topological vector spaces), then it makes sense to ask whether all linear maps are continuous. It turns out that for maps defined on infinite-dimensional topological vector spaces (e.g., infinite-dimensional normed spaces), the answer is generally no: there exist discontinuous linear maps. If the domain of definition is complete, it is trickier; such maps can be proven to exist, but the proof relies on the axiom of choice and does not provide an explicit example.
Let X and Y be two normed spaces and
f:X\toY
\left(e1,e2,\ldots,en\right)
f
\|f(x)-f(x')\|=\|f(x-x')\|\leqK\|x-x'\|
\epsilon>0,
\delta\leq\epsilon/K
f(B(x,\delta))\subseteqB(f(x),\epsilon)
B(x,\delta)
B(f(x),\epsilon)
x
f(x)
If X is infinite-dimensional, this proof will fail as there is no guarantee that the supremum M exists. If Y is the zero space, the only map between X and Y is the zero map which is trivially continuous. In all other cases, when X is infinite-dimensional and Y is not the zero space, one can find a discontinuous map from X to Y.
Examples of discontinuous linear maps are easy to construct in spaces that are not complete; on any Cauchy sequence
ei
T
\|T(ei)\|/\|ei\|
For example, consider the space
X
X
n\geq1
as
n\toinfty
T(fn)\toT(0)=0
T
X
X*
X\toX
The fact that the domain is not complete here is important: discontinuous operators on complete spaces require a little more work.
An algebraic basis for the real numbers as a vector space over the rationals is known as a Hamel basis (note that some authors use this term in a broader sense to mean an algebraic basis of any vector space). Note that any two noncommensurable numbers, say 1 and
\pi
f:\R\toR
f(\pi)=0,
\R
\pi
f(\pi)=0.
\Q
\R
This example can be extended into a general theorem about the existence of discontinuous linear maps on any infinite-dimensional normed space (as long as the codomain is not trivial).
Discontinuous linear maps can be proven to exist more generally, even if the space is complete. Let X and Y be normed spaces over the field K where
K=\R
K=\Complex.
g(x)=f(x)y0
y0
If X is infinite-dimensional, to show the existence of a linear functional which is not continuous then amounts to constructing f which is not bounded. For that, consider a sequence (en)n (
n\geq1
n=1,2,\ldots
Notice that by using the fact that any set of linearly independent vectors can be completed to a basis, we implicitly used the axiom of choice, which was not needed for the concrete example in the previous section.
As noted above, the axiom of choice (AC) is used in the general existence theorem of discontinuous linear maps. In fact, there are no constructive examples of discontinuous linear maps with complete domain (for example, Banach spaces). In analysis as it is usually practiced by working mathematicians, the axiom of choice is always employed (it is an axiom of ZFC set theory); thus, to the analyst, all infinite-dimensional topological vector spaces admit discontinuous linear maps.
On the other hand, in 1970 Robert M. Solovay exhibited a model of set theory in which every set of reals is measurable.[1] This implies that there are no discontinuous linear real functions. Clearly AC does not hold in the model.
Solovay's result shows that it is not necessary to assume that all infinite-dimensional vector spaces admit discontinuous linear maps, and there are schools of analysis which adopt a more constructivist viewpoint. For example, H. G. Garnir, in searching for so-called "dream spaces" (topological vector spaces on which every linear map into a normed space is continuous), was led to adopt ZF + DC + BP (dependent choice is a weakened form and the Baire property is a negation of strong AC) as his axioms to prove the Garnir–Wright closed graph theorem which states, among other things, that any linear map from an F-space to a TVS is continuous. Going to the extreme of constructivism, there is Ceitin's theorem, which states that every function is continuous (this is to be understood in the terminology of constructivism, according to which only representable functions are considered to be functions).[2] Such stances are held by only a small minority of working mathematicians.
The upshot is that the existence of discontinuous linear maps depends on AC; it is consistent with set theory without AC that there are no discontinuous linear maps on complete spaces. In particular, no concrete construction such as the derivative can succeed in defining a discontinuous linear map everywhere on a complete space.
Many naturally occurring linear discontinuous operators are closed, a class of operators which share some of the features of continuous operators. It makes sense to ask which linear operators on a given space are closed. The closed graph theorem asserts that an everywhere-defined closed operator on a complete domain is continuous, so to obtain a discontinuous closed operator, one must permit operators which are not defined everywhere.
To be more concrete, let
T
X
Y
\operatorname{Dom}(T),
T:\operatorname{Dom}(T)\subseteqX\toY.
\operatorname{Dom}(T).
If the graph
\Gamma(T)
T
X x Y,
\overline{\Gamma(T)}
X x Y.
\overline{\Gamma(T)}
\overline{T},
T
\overline{T}
T.
So the natural question to ask about linear operators that are not everywhere-defined is whether they are closable. The answer is, "not necessarily"; indeed, every infinite-dimensional normed space admits linear operators that are not closable. As in the case of discontinuous operators considered above, the proof requires the axiom of choice and so is in general nonconstructive, though again, if X is not complete, there are constructible examples.
In fact, there is even an example of a linear operator whose graph has closure all of
X x Y.
\R
\R
X x Y,
The dual space of a topological vector space is the collection of continuous linear maps from the space into the underlying field. Thus the failure of some linear maps to be continuous for infinite-dimensional normed spaces implies that for these spaces, one needs to distinguish the algebraic dual space from the continuous dual space which is then a proper subset. It illustrates the fact that an extra dose of caution is needed in doing analysis on infinite-dimensional spaces as compared to finite-dimensional ones.
The argument for the existence of discontinuous linear maps on normed spaces can be generalized to all metrizable topological vector spaces, especially to all Fréchet spaces, but there exist infinite-dimensional locally convex topological vector spaces such that every functional is continuous.[3] On the other hand, the Hahn–Banach theorem, which applies to all locally convex spaces, guarantees the existence of many continuous linear functionals, and so a large dual space. In fact, to every convex set, the Minkowski gauge associates a continuous linear functional. The upshot is that spaces with fewer convex sets have fewer functionals, and in the worst-case scenario, a space may have no functionals at all other than the zero functional. This is the case for the Lp(\R,dx)
0<p<1,
Lp
0<p<1
Another such example is the space of real-valued measurable functions on the unit interval with quasinorm given by
One can consider even more general spaces. For example, the existence of a homomorphism between complete separable metric groups can also be shown nonconstructively.