Constructible universe explained
Constructible universe should not be confused with Gödel metric.
In mathematics, in set theory, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by
, is a particular
class of
sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets.
is the union of the
constructible hierarchy
. It was introduced by
Kurt Gödel in his 1938 paper "The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis".
[1] In this paper, he proved that the constructible universe is an
inner model of ZF set theory (that is, of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the
axiom of choice excluded), and also that the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis are true in the constructible universe. This shows that both propositions are
consistent with the basic
axioms of set theory, if ZF itself is consistent. Since many other theorems only hold in systems in which one or both of the propositions is true, their consistency is an important result.
What L is
can be thought of as being built in "stages" resembling the construction of
von Neumann universe,
. The stages are indexed by
ordinals. In von Neumann's universe, at a
successor stage, one takes
to be the set of
all subsets of the previous stage,
. By contrast, in Gödel's constructible universe
, one uses
only those subsets of the previous stage that are:
- definable by a formula in the formal language of set theory,
- with parameters from the previous stage and,
- with the quantifiers interpreted to range over the previous stage.
By limiting oneself to sets defined only in terms of what has already been constructed, one ensures that the resulting sets will be constructed in a way that is independent of the peculiarities of the surrounding model of set theory and contained in any such model.
Define the Def operator:[2]
is defined by transfinite recursion as follows:
L\alpha:=\operatorname{Def}(L\alpha).
is a
limit ordinal, then
Here
means
precedes
.
Here
Ord denotes the
class of all ordinals.
If
is an element of
, then
z=\{y\inL\alpha and y\inz\}\inrm{Def}(L\alpha)=L\alpha+1
.
[3] So
is a subset of
, which is a subset of the
power set of
. Consequently, this is a tower of nested
transitive sets. But
itself is a
proper class.
The elements of
are called "constructible" sets; and
itself is the "constructible universe". The "
axiom of constructibility", aka "
", says that every set (of
) is constructible, i.e. in
.
Additional facts about the sets Lα
An equivalent definition for
is:
For any finite ordinal
, the sets
and
are the same (whether
equals
or not), and thus
=
: their elements are exactly the
hereditarily finite sets. Equality beyond this point does not hold. Even in models of
ZFC in which
equals
,
is a proper subset of
, and thereafter
is a proper subset of the power set of
for all
. On the other hand,
does imply that
equals
if
, for example if
is inaccessible. More generally,
implies
=
for all infinite cardinals
.
If
is an infinite ordinal then there is a
bijection between
and
, and the bijection is constructible. So these sets are
equinumerous in any model of set theory that includes them.
As defined above,
is the set of subsets of
defined by
formulas (with respect to the
Levy hierarchy, i.e., formulas of set theory containing only
bounded quantifiers) that use as parameters only
and its elements.
[4] Another definition, due to Gödel, characterizes each
as the intersection of the power set of
with the closure of
under a collection of nine explicit functions, similar to
Gödel operations. This definition makes no reference to definability.
All arithmetical subsets of
and relations on
belong to
(because the arithmetic definition gives one in
). Conversely, any subset of
belonging to
is arithmetical (because elements of
can be coded by natural numbers in such a way that
is definable, i.e., arithmetic). On the other hand,
already contains certain non-arithmetical subsets of
, such as the set of (natural numbers coding) true arithmetical statements (this can be defined from
so it is in
).
All hyperarithmetical subsets of
and relations on
belong to
(where
stands for the Church–Kleene ordinal), and conversely any subset of
that belongs to
is hyperarithmetical.
[5] L is a standard inner model of ZFC
is a standard model, i.e.
is a
transitive class and the interpretation uses the real element relationship, so it is
well-founded.
is an inner model, i.e. it contains all the ordinal numbers of
and it has no "extra" sets beyond those in
. However
might be strictly a subclass of
.
is a model of
ZFC, which means that it satisfies the following
axioms:
contains some element
such that
and
are disjoint sets.
is a substructure of
, which is well founded, so
is well founded. In particular, if
, then by the transitivity of
,
. If we use this same
as in
, then it is still disjoint from
because we are using the same element relation and no new sets were added.
If
and
are in
and they have the same elements in
, then by
's transitivity, they have the same elements (in
). So they are equal (in
and thus in
).
\{\}=L0=\{y\midy\inL0\landy=y\}
, which is in
. So
. Since the element relation is the same and no new elements were added, this is the empty set of
.
,
are sets, then
is a set.
If
and
, then there is some ordinal
such that
and
. Then
\{x,y\}=\{s\mids\inL\alpha and (s=x or s=y)\}\inL\alpha+1
. Thus
and it has the same meaning for
as for
.
there is a set
whose elements are precisely the elements of the elements of
.
If
, then its elements are in
and their elements are also in
. So
is a subset of
. Then
y=\{s\mids\inL\alpha and there exists z\inx such that s\inz\}\inL\alpha+1
. Thus
.
such that
is in
and whenever
is in
, so is the union
.
Transfinite induction can be used to show each ordinal
is in
. In particular,
and thus
.
- Axiom of separation: Given any set
and any proposition
,
\{x\midx\inS and P(x,z1,\ldots,zn)\}
is a set.
By induction on subformulas of
, one can show that there is an
such that
contains
and
and (
is true in
if and only if
is true in
), the latter is called the "
reflection principle"). So
\{x\midx\inS and P(x,z1,\ldots,zn) holds in L\}
=
\{x\midx\inL\alpha and x\inS and P(x,z1,\ldots,zn) holds in L\alpha\}\inL\alpha+1
. Thus the subset is in
.
[6] - Axiom of replacement: Given any set
and any mapping (formally defined as a proposition
where
and
implies
),
\{y\mid there exists x\inS such that P(x,y)\}
is a set.
Let
be the formula that relativizes
to
, i.e. all quantifiers in
are restricted to
.
is a much more complex formula than
, but it is still a finite formula, and since
was a mapping over
,
must be a mapping over
; thus we can apply replacement in
to
. So
\{y\midy\inL and there exists x\inS such that P(x,y) holds in L\}
=
\{y\midthere exists x\inS such that Q(x,y)\}
is a set in
and a subclass of
. Again using the axiom of replacement in
, we can show that there must be an
such that this set is a subset of
. Then one can use the axiom of separation in
to finish showing that it is an element of
there exists a set
, such that the elements of
are precisely the subsets of
.
In general, some subsets of a set in
will not be in
So the whole power set of a set in
will usually not be in
. What we need here is to show that the intersection of the power set with
is in
. Use replacement in
to show that there is an α such that the intersection is a subset of
. Then the intersection is
\{z\midz\inL\alpha and z is a subset of x\}\inL\alpha+1
. Thus the required set is in
.
of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, there is a set
(a choice set for
) containing exactly one element from each member of
.
One can show that there is a definable well-ordering of, in particular based on ordering all sets in
by their definitions and by the rank they appear at. So one chooses the least element of each member of
to form
using the axioms of union and separation in
Notice that the proof that
is a model of ZFC only requires that
be a model of ZF, i.e. we do
not assume that the axiom of choice holds in
.
L is absolute and minimal
If
is any standard model of ZF sharing the same ordinals as
, then the
defined in
is the same as the
defined in
. In particular,
is the same in
and
, for any ordinal
. And the same formulas and parameters in
produce the same constructible sets in
.
Furthermore, since
is a subclass of
and, similarly,
is a subclass of
,
is the smallest class containing all the ordinals that is a standard model of ZF. Indeed,
is the intersection of all such classes.
If there is a set
in
that is a
standard model of ZF, and the ordinal
is the set of ordinals that occur in
, then
is the
of
. If there is a set that is a standard model of ZF, then the smallest such set is such a
. This set is called the
minimal model of ZFC. Using the downward
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, one can show that the minimal model (if it exists) is a countable set.
Of course, any consistent theory must have a model, so even within the minimal model of set theory there are sets that are models of ZF (assuming ZF is consistent). However, those set models are non-standard. In particular, they do not use the normal element relation and they are not well founded.
Because both "
constructed within
" and "
constructed within
" result in the real
, and both the
of
and the
of
are the real
, we get that
is true in
and in any
that is a model of ZF. However,
does not hold in any other standard model of ZF.
L and large cardinals
Since
, properties of ordinals that depend on the absence of a function or other structure (i.e.
formulas) are preserved when going down from
to
. Hence initial ordinals of cardinals remain initial in
.
Regular ordinals remain regular in
. Weak
limit cardinals become strong limit cardinals in
because the generalized continuum hypothesis holds in
. Weakly
inaccessible cardinals become strongly inaccessible. Weakly
Mahlo cardinals become strongly Mahlo. And more generally, any
large cardinal property weaker than
0 (see the
list of large cardinal properties) will be retained in
.
However,
is false in
even if true in
. So all the large cardinals whose existence implies
cease to have those large cardinal properties, but retain the properties weaker than
which they also possess. For example,
measurable cardinals cease to be measurable but remain Mahlo in
.
If
holds in
, then there is a
closed unbounded class of ordinals that are
indiscernible in
. While some of these are not even initial ordinals in
, they have all the large cardinal properties weaker than
in
. Furthermore, any strictly increasing class function from the class of
indiscernibles to itself can be extended in a unique way to an elementary embedding of
into
. This gives
a nice structure of repeating segments.
L can be well-ordered
There are various ways of well-ordering
. Some of these involve the
"fine structure" of
, which was first described by
Ronald Bjorn Jensen in his 1972 paper entitled "The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy". Instead of explaining the fine structure, we will give an outline of how
could be well-ordered using only the definition given above.
Suppose
and
are two different sets in
and we wish to determine whether
or
. If
first appears in
and
first appears in
and
is different from
, then let if and only if
. Henceforth, we suppose that
.
The stage
uses formulas with parameters from
to define the sets
and
. If one discounts (for the moment) the parameters, the formulas can be given a standard
Gödel numbering by the natural numbers. If
is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define
, and
is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define
, and
is different from
, then let if and only if
in the Gödel numbering. Henceforth, we suppose that
.
Suppose that
uses
parameters from
. Suppose
is the sequence of parameters that can be used with
to define
, and
does the same for
. Then let
if and only if either
or (
and
) or (
and
and
), etc. This is called the reverse
lexicographic ordering; if there are multiple sequences of parameters that define one of the sets, we choose the least one under this ordering. It being understood that each parameter's possible values are ordered according to the restriction of the ordering of
to
, so this definition involves transfinite recursion on
.
The well-ordering of the values of single parameters is provided by the inductive hypothesis of the transfinite induction. The values of
-tuples of parameters are well-ordered by the product ordering. The formulas with parameters are well-ordered by the ordered sum (by Gödel numbers) of well-orderings. And
is well-ordered by the ordered sum (indexed by
) of the orderings on
.
Notice that this well-ordering can be defined within
itself by a formula of set theory with no parameters, only the free-variables
and
. And this formula gives the same
truth value regardless of whether it is evaluated in
,
, or
(some other standard model of ZF with the same ordinals) and we will suppose that the formula is false if either
or
is not in
.
It is well known that the axiom of choice is equivalent to the ability to well-order every set. Being able to well-order the proper class
(as we have done here with
) is equivalent to the
axiom of global choice, which is more powerful than the ordinary
axiom of choice because it also covers proper classes of non-empty sets.
has a reflection principle
Proving that the axiom of separation, axiom of replacement, and axiom of choice hold in
requires (at least as shown above) the use of a
reflection principle for
. Here we describe such a principle.
By induction on
, we can use ZF in
to prove that for any ordinal
, there is an ordinal
such that for any sentence
with
in
and containing fewer than
symbols (counting a constant symbol for an element of
as one symbol) we get that
holds in
if and only if it holds in
.
The generalized continuum hypothesis holds in L
Let
, and let
be any constructible subset of
. Then there is some
with
, so for some formula
and some
drawn from
. By the downward
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem and
Mostowski collapse, there must be some transitive set
containing
and some
, and having the same first-order theory as
with the
substituted for the
; and this
will have the same cardinal as
. Since
is true in
, it is also true in, so
for some
having the same cardinal as
. And
T=\{x\inL\beta:x\inS\wedge\Phi(x,zi)\}=\{x\inL\gamma:x\inS\wedge\Phi(x,wi)\}
because
and
have the same theory. So
is in fact in
.
So all the constructible subsets of an infinite set
have ranks with (at most) the same cardinal
as the rank of
; it follows that if
is the initial ordinal for
, then
L\capl{P}(S)\subseteqL\delta
serves as the "power set" of
within
Thus this "power set"
. And this in turn means that the "power set" of
has cardinal at most
. Assuming
itself has cardinal
, the "power set" must then have cardinal exactly
. But this is precisely the generalized continuum hypothesis relativized to
.
Constructible sets are definable from the ordinals
There is a formula of set theory that expresses the idea that
. It has only free variables for
and
. Using this we can expand the definition of each constructible set. If
, then
S=\{y\midy\inL\alpha and \Phi(y,z1,\ldots,zn) holds in (L\alpha,\in)\}
for some formula
and some
in
. This is equivalent to saying that: for all
,
if and only if [there exists <math>X</math> such that <math>X=L_\alpha</math> and <math>y \in X</math> and <math>\Psi(X,y,z_1,\ldots,z_n)</math>] where
is the result of restricting each quantifier in
to
. Notice that each
for some
. Combine formulas for the
's with the formula for
and apply existential quantifiers over the
's outside and one gets a formula that defines the constructible set
using only the ordinals
that appear in expressions like
as parameters.
Example: The set
is constructible. It is the unique set
that satisfies the formula:
where
is short for:
Actually, even this complex formula has been simplified from what the instructions given in the first paragraph would yield. But the point remains, there is a formula of set theory that is true only for the desired constructible set
and that contains parameters only for ordinals.
Relative constructibility
Sometimes it is desirable to find a model of set theory that is narrow like
, but that includes or is influenced by a set that is not constructible. This gives rise to the concept of relative constructibility, of which there are two flavors, denoted by
and
.
The class
for a non-constructible set
is the intersection of all classes that are standard models of set theory and contain
and all the ordinals.
is defined by transfinite recursion as follows:
= the smallest transitive set containing
as an element, i.e. the transitive closure of
.
=
is a limit ordinal, then
Lλ(A)=cup\alphaL\alpha(A)
.
.
If
contains a well-ordering of the transitive closure of
, then this can be extended to a well-ordering of
. Otherwise, the axiom of choice will fail in
.
A common example is
, the smallest model that contains all the real numbers, which is used extensively in modern
descriptive set theory.
The class
is the class of sets whose construction is influenced by
, where
may be a (presumably non-constructible) set or a proper class. The definition of this class uses
, which is the same as
except instead of evaluating the truth of formulas
in the model
, one uses the model
where
is a unary predicate. The intended interpretation of
is
. Then the definition of
is exactly that of
only with
replaced by
.
is always a model of the axiom of choice. Even if
is a set,
is not necessarily itself a member of
, although it always is if
is a set of ordinals.
The sets in
or
are usually not actually constructible, and the properties of these models may be quite different from the properties of
itself.
See also
Notes
- Gödel 1938.
- K. J. Devlin, "An introduction to the fine structure of the constructible hierarchy" (1974). Accessed 20 February 2023.
- K. J. Devlin, Constructibility (1984), ch. 2, "The Constructible Universe, p.58. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer-Verlag.
- K. Devlin 1975, An Introduction to the Fine Structure of the Constructible Hierarchy (p.2). Accessed 2021-05-12.
- Barwise 1975, page 60 (comment following proof of theorem 5.9)
- P. Odifreddi, Classical Recursion Theory, pp.427. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics
References
- Book: Barwise, Jon . Jon Barwise . Admissible Sets and Structures . 1975 . Berlin . Springer-Verlag . 0-387-07451-1 . registration .
- Book: Devlin, Keith J.. Keith Devlin . Constructibility . 1984 . Berlin . Springer-Verlag . 0-387-13258-9.
- Book: Felgner, Ulrich. 1971. Models of ZF-Set Theory. Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag. 3-540-05591-6.
- 10.1073/pnas.24.12.556 . Gödel . Kurt . The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis . Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America . 24 . 12 . 1938. 556–557 . National Academy of Sciences . 16577857 . 1077160. 87239. 1938PNAS...24..556G . free .
- Book: Gödel, Kurt
. 0002514. The Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis. Annals of Mathematics Studies. 3. Princeton University Press. Princeton, N. J.. 1940. 978-0-691-07927-1.
- Book: Jech, Thomas. Thomas Jech. 2002. Set Theory. 3rd millennium. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer. 3-540-44085-2.