Choice function explained
A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function f that is defined on some collection X of nonempty sets and assigns some element of each set S in that collection to S by f(S); f(S) maps S to some element of S. In other words, f is a choice function for X if and only if it belongs to the direct product of X.
An example
Let X = . Then the function f defined by f = 7, f = 9 and f = 2 is a choice function on X.
History and importance
Ernst Zermelo (1904) introduced choice functions as well as the axiom of choice (AC) and proved the well-ordering theorem,[1] which states that every set can be well-ordered. AC states that every set of nonempty sets has a choice function. A weaker form of AC, the axiom of countable choice (ACω) states that every countable set of nonempty sets has a choice function. However, in the absence of either AC or ACω, some sets can still be shown to have a choice function.
is a
finite set of nonempty sets, then one can construct a choice function for
by picking one element from each member of
This requires only finitely many choices, so neither AC or AC
ω is needed.
is a nonempty set, and the
union
is well-ordered, then one may choose the least element of each member of
. In this case, it was possible to simultaneously well-order every member of
by making just one choice of a well-order of the union, so neither AC nor AC
ω was needed. (This example shows that the well-ordering theorem implies AC. The
converse is also true, but less trivial.)
Choice function of a multivalued map
Given two sets X and Y, let F be a multivalued map from X to Y (equivalently,
is a function from
X to the
power set of
Y).
A function
is said to be a
selection of
F, if:
The existence of more regular choice functions, namely continuous or measurable selections is important in the theory of differential inclusions, optimal control, and mathematical economics.[2] See Selection theorem.
Bourbaki tau function
Nicolas Bourbaki used epsilon calculus for their foundations that had a
symbol that could be interpreted as choosing an object (if one existed) that satisfies a given proposition. So if
is a predicate, then
is one particular object that satisfies
(if one exists, otherwise it returns an arbitrary object). Hence we may obtain quantifiers from the choice function, for example
was equivalent to
.
[3] However, Bourbaki's choice operator is stronger than usual: it's a global choice operator. That is, it implies the axiom of global choice.[4] Hilbert realized this when introducing epsilon calculus.[5]
See also
Notes and References
- Ernst. Zermelo. 1904. Beweis, dass jede Menge wohlgeordnet werden kann. Mathematische Annalen. 59. 4. 514–16. 10.1007/BF01445300.
- Book: Border
, Kim C.
. Fixed Point Theorems with Applications to Economics and Game Theory . 1989 . Cambridge University Press . 0-521-26564-9 .
- Book: Bourbaki, Nicolas. Elements of Mathematics: Theory of Sets. 0-201-00634-0.
- John Harrison, "The Bourbaki View" eprint.
- "Here, moreover, we come upon a very remarkable circumstance, namely, that all of these transfinite axioms are derivable from a single axiom, one that also contains the core of one of the most attacked axioms in the literature of mathematics, namely, the axiom of choice:
, where
is the transfinite logical choice function." Hilbert (1925), “On the Infinite”, excerpted in Jean van Heijenoort, From Frege to Gödel, p. 382. From nCatLab.