In Euclidean geometry, Ceva's theorem is a theorem about triangles. Given a triangle, let the lines be drawn from the vertices to a common point (not on one of the sides of), to meet opposite sides at respectively. (The segments are known as cevians.) Then, using signed lengths of segments,
\overline{AF | |
Ceva's theorem is a theorem of affine geometry, in the sense that it may be stated and proved without using the concepts of angles, areas, and lengths (except for the ratio of the lengths of two line segments that are collinear). It is therefore true for triangles in any affine plane over any field.
A slightly adapted converse is also true: If points are chosen on respectively so that
\overline{AF | |
The theorem is often attributed to Giovanni Ceva, who published it in his 1678 work De lineis rectis. But it was proven much earlier by Yusuf Al-Mu'taman ibn Hűd, an eleventh-century king of Zaragoza.[1]
Associated with the figures are several terms derived from Ceva's name: cevian (the lines are the cevians of), cevian triangle (the triangle is the cevian triangle of); cevian nest, anticevian triangle, Ceva conjugate. (Ceva is pronounced Chay'va; cevian is pronounced chev'ian.)
The theorem is very similar to Menelaus' theorem in that their equations differ only in sign. By re-writing each in terms of cross-ratios, the two theorems may be seen as projective duals.[2]
Several proofs of the theorem have been given.[3] [4] Two proofs are given in the following.
The first one is very elementary, using only basic properties of triangle areas. However, several cases have to be considered, depending on the position of the point .
The second proof uses barycentric coordinates and vectors, but is somehow more natural and not case dependent. Moreover, it works in any affine plane over any field.
First, the sign of the left-hand side is positive since either all three of the ratios are positive, the case where is inside the triangle (upper diagram), or one is positive and the other two are negative, the case is outside the triangle (lower diagram shows one case).
To check the magnitude, note that the area of a triangle of a given height is proportional to its base. So
|\triangleBOD| | = | |
|\triangleCOD| |
\overline{BD | |
\overline{BD | |
- | \triangle BOD |
- | \triangle COD |
\overline{CE | |
\overline{AF | |
\left| | \overline{AF |
The theorem can also be proven easily using Menelaus's theorem.[5] From the transversal of triangle,
\overline{AB | |
\overline{BA | |
The converse follows as a corollary.[3] Let be given on the lines so that the equation holds. Let meet at and let be the point where crosses . Then by the theorem, the equation also holds for . Comparing the two,
\overline{AF | |
Given three points that are not collinear, and a point, that belongs to the same plane, the barycentric coordinates of with respect of are the unique three numbers
λA,λB,λC
λA+λB+λC=1,
\overrightarrow{XO}=λA\overrightarrow{XA}+λB\overrightarrow{XB}+λC\overrightarrow{XC},
For Ceva's theorem, the point is supposed to not belong to any line passing through two vertices of the triangle. This implies that
λAλBλC\ne0.
If one takes for the intersection of the lines and (see figures), the last equation may be rearranged into
\overrightarrow{FO}-λC\overrightarrow{FC}=λA\overrightarrow{FA}+λB\overrightarrow{FB}.
λA\overrightarrow{FA}+λB\overrightarrow{FB}=0.
\overline{AF | |
The same reasoning shows
\overline{BD | |
The theorem can be generalized to higher-dimensional simplexes using barycentric coordinates. Define a cevian of an -simplex as a ray from each vertex to a point on the opposite -face (facet). Then the cevians are concurrent if and only if a mass distribution can be assigned to the vertices such that each cevian intersects the opposite facet at its center of mass. Moreover, the intersection point of the cevians is the center of mass of the simplex.[6] [7]
Another generalization to higher-dimensional simplexes extends the conclusion of Ceva's theorem that the product of certain ratios is 1. Starting from a point in a simplex, a point is defined inductively on each -face. This point is the foot of a cevian that goes from the vertex opposite the -face, in a -face that contains it, through the point already defined on this -face. Each of these points divides the face on which it lies into lobes. Given a cycle of pairs of lobes, the product of the ratios of the volumes of the lobes in each pair is 1.[8]
Routh's theorem gives the area of the triangle formed by three cevians in the case that they are not concurrent. Ceva's theorem can be obtained from it by setting the area equal to zero and solving.
The analogue of the theorem for general polygons in the plane has been known since the early nineteenth century.[9] The theorem has also been generalized to triangles on other surfaces of constant curvature.[10]
The theorem also has a well-known generalization to spherical and hyperbolic geometry, replacing the lengths in the ratios with their sines and hyperbolic sines, respectively.