Argumentum ad populum explained

In argumentation theory, an (Latin for "appeal to the people")[1] is a fallacious argument which is based on claiming a truth or affirming something is good because many people think so.[2]

Alternative names

Other names for the fallacy include:

Description

is a type of informal fallacy, specifically a fallacy of relevance,[3] [4] and is similar to an argument from authority (argumentum ad verecundiam).[5] [6] [7] It uses an appeal to the beliefs, tastes, or values of a group of people,[8] stating that because a certain opinion or attitude is held by a majority, or even everyone, it is therefore correct.[9]

Appeals to popularity are common in commercial advertising that portrays products as desirable because they are used by many people or associated with popular sentiments[10] instead of communicating the merits of the products themselves.

The inverse argument, that something that is unpopular must be flawed, is also a form of this fallacy.[11]

The fallacy is similar in structure to certain other fallacies that involve a confusion between the "justification" of a belief and its "widespread acceptance" by a given group of people. When an argument uses the appeal to the beliefs of a group of experts, it takes on the form of an appeal to authority; if the appeal relates to the beliefs of a group of respected elders or the members of one's community over a long time, then it takes on the form of an appeal to tradition.

Scholarship

The philosopher Irving Copi defined differently from an appeal to popular opinion itself,[12] as an attempt to rouse the "emotions and enthusiasms of the multitude".[13]

Douglas N. Walton argues that appeals to popular opinion can be logically valid in some cases, such as in political dialogue within a democracy.

Reversals

In some circumstances, a person may argue that the fact that Y people believe X to be true implies that X is false. This line of thought is closely related to the appeal to spite fallacy given that it invokes a person's contempt for the general populace or something about the general populace to persuade them that most are wrong about X. This ad populum reversal commits the same logical flaw as the original fallacy given that the idea "X is true" is inherently separate from the idea that "Y people believe X": "Y people believe in X as true, purely because Y people believe in it, and not because of any further considerations. Therefore X must be false." While Y people can believe X to be true for fallacious reasons, X might still be true. Their motivations for believing X do not affect whether X is true or false.

Y=most people, a given quantity of people, people of a particular demographic.

X=a statement that can be true or false.

Examples:

In general, the reversal usually goes: Most people believe A and B are both true. B is false. Thus, A is false. The similar fallacy of chronological snobbery is not to be confused with the ad populum reversal. Chronological snobbery is the claim that if belief in both X and Y was popularly held in the past and if Y was recently proved to be untrue then X must also be untrue. That line of argument is based on a belief in historical progress and not—like the ad populum reversal is—on whether or not X and/or Y is currently popular.

Valid uses

Appeals to public opinion are valid in situations where consensus is the determining factor for the validity of a statement, such as linguistic usage and definitions of words.

Language

Linguistic descriptivists argue that correct grammar, spelling, and expressions are defined by the language's speakers, especially in languages which do not have a central governing body. According to this viewpoint, if an incorrect expression is commonly used, it becomes correct. In contrast, linguistic prescriptivists believe that incorrect expressions are incorrect regardless of how many people use them. [14]

Mathematics

Special functions are mathematical functions that have well-established names and mathematical notations due to their significance in mathematics and other scientific fields.

There is no formal definition of what makes a function a special function; instead, the term special function is defined by consensus. Functions generally considered to be special functions include logarithms, trigonometric functions, and the Bessel functions.

Further reading

External links

Notes and References

  1. Book: Walton, Douglas N.. Appeal to Popular Opinion. 1999. The Pennsylvania State University Press. 0-271-01818-6. 61–62. 98031384. Douglas N. Walton.
  2. Web site: Ayala . Maite . Falacia ad populum: definición, características, ejemplos . Lifeder . 1 August 2021 . es . 11 January 2021.
  3. Encyclopedia: Rescher . Nicholas . Schagrin . Morton L. . Fallacy . December 21, 2019 . Encyclopædia Britannica.
  4. Book: Hitchcock, David . On Reasoning and Argument: Essays in Informal Logic and on Critical Thinking . 2017 . Springer . 978-3-319-53561-6 . 406 . 2017930649.
  5. Encyclopedia: Hansen . Hans . Fallacies . Stanford University . May 29, 2015 . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  6. Book: Epstein . Richard L. . Critical Thinking . Rooney . Michael . 2017 . Advanced Reasoning Forum . 978-1-938421-32-7 . 5th . Socorro, N.M. . 76 . 2017471425.
  7. Book: Engel, S. Morris . Fallacies and Pitfalls of Language: The Language Trap . 1994 . Dover Publications . 0-486-28274-0 . New York . 145–6 . 94019770 . S. Morris Engel.
  8. Book: Van Vleet, Jacob E. . Informal Logical Fallacies: A Brief Guide . 2011 . University Press of America . 978-0-7618-5432-6 . 20 . 2016448028.
  9. Book: Woods, John . Gabbay . D.M. . Pelletier . F.J. . Woods . J. . Logic: A History of its Central Concepts . 2012 . North-Holland . 978-0-08-093170-8 . 561 . https://books.google.com/books?id=9mwtRDXVM2wC&q=%22ad+populum%22 . A History of the Fallacies in Western Logic . Handbook of the History of Logic.
  10. Book: Walton, Douglas N. . Informal Logic: A Handbook for Critical Argumentation . 1989 . Cambridge University Press . 0-521-37032-9 . 84 . Appeals to emotion . 88030762 . https://books.google.com/books?id=kswimguc5uYC&q=%22ad-populum%22.
  11. Book: Govier, Trudy . A Practical Study of Argument . 2009 . Cengage Learning . 978-0-495-60340-5 . 7th . 162 . Trudy Govier.
  12. Book: Freeman, James B. . Hansen . Hans V. . Pinto . Robert C. . Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings . 1995 . The Pennsylvania State University Press . 0-271-01416-4 . 266 . https://books.google.com/books?id=ftCx1ViH4B0C&q=%22ad+populum%22+copi . The Appeal to Popularity and Presumption by Common Knowledge.
  13. Book: Walton, Douglas N.. The Place of Emotion in Argument. 1992. The Pennsylvania State University Press. 0-271-00833-4. 66–7. Argumentum Ad Populum. 91030515. Douglas N. Walton. https://books.google.com/books?id=eZ6Tmr2PaHcC&pg=PA65.
  14. Web site: Editing Tips: Prescriptivism vs. Descriptivism . April 15, 2021 .