Well-ordering theorem should not be confused with Well-ordering principle.
In mathematics, the well-ordering theorem, also known as Zermelo's theorem, states that every set can be well-ordered. A set X is well-ordered by a strict total order if every non-empty subset of X has a least element under the ordering. The well-ordering theorem together with Zorn's lemma are the most important mathematical statements that are equivalent to the axiom of choice (often called AC, see also).[1] [2] Ernst Zermelo introduced the axiom of choice as an "unobjectionable logical principle" to prove the well-ordering theorem.[3] One can conclude from the well-ordering theorem that every set is susceptible to transfinite induction, which is considered by mathematicians to be a powerful technique.[3] One famous consequence of the theorem is the Banach–Tarski paradox.
Georg Cantor considered the well-ordering theorem to be a "fundamental principle of thought".[4] However, it is considered difficult or even impossible to visualize a well-ordering of
R
The axiom of choice is obviously true, the well-ordering principle obviously false, and who can tell about Zorn's lemma?
The well-ordering theorem follows from the axiom of choice as follows.[7]
Let the set we are trying to well-order be, and letA
be a choice function for the family of non-empty subsets off
. For every ordinalA
, define an element\alpha
that is ina\alpha
by settingA
if this complementa\alpha = f(A\smallsetminus\{a\xi\mid\xi<\alpha\})
is nonempty, or leaveA\smallsetminus\{a\xi\mid\xi<\alpha\}
undefined if it is. That is,a\alpha
is chosen from the set of elements ofa\alpha
that have not yet been assigned a place in the ordering (or undefined if the entirety ofA
has been successfully enumerated). Then the orderA
on<
defined byA
if and only ifa\alpha<a\beta
(in the usual well-order of the ordinals) is a well-order of\alpha<\beta
as desired, of order typeA
.\sup\{\alpha\mida\alphaisdefined\}
The axiom of choice can be proven from the well-ordering theorem as follows.
To make a choice function for a collection of non-empty sets,
E
E
X
X
R
S
E
S
S
R
E
An essential point of this proof is that it involves only a single arbitrary choice, that of
R
S
E
S
S
E
. An introduction to the theory of functional equations and inequalities . 14 . Berlin . Springer . 978-3-7643-8748-8 . 2009 . Marek Kuczma.
. Encyclopaedia of Mathematics: Supplement . 2001 . Michiel Hazewinkel . 458 . Berlin . Springer . 1-4020-0198-3 .
. Stewart Shapiro . 1991 . Foundations Without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-Order Logic . New York . Oxford University Press . 0-19-853391-8 .