The Varieties of Religious Experience explained

The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature
Title Orig:The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature, Being the Gifford Lectures on Natural Religion Delivered at Edinburgh in 1901–1902
Author:William James
Country:United States
Language:English
Subjects:Philosophy of religion
Psychology of religion
Publisher:Longmans, Green & Co.
Pub Date:1902
Media Type:Print
Pages:534
Congress:BR110.J3 1902a
Followed By:Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking (1907)

The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature is a book by Harvard University psychologist and philosopher William James. It comprises his edited Gifford Lectures on natural theology, which were delivered at the University of Edinburgh, Scotland between 1901 and 1902. The lectures concerned the psychological study of individual private religious experiences and mysticism, and used a range of examples to identify commonalities in religious experiences across traditions.

Soon after its publication, Varieties entered the Western canon of psychology and philosophy and has remained in print for over a century.

James later developed his philosophy of pragmatism. There are many overlapping ideas in Varieties and his 1907 book Pragmatism.[1]

Historical context

Psychology of religion

In the 1890s, a "new psychology" emerged in European and American universities which coincided with the establishment of many new psychology laboratories and the appointment of faculty in psychology. New psychology's novelty was encapsulated by its distinction from philosophy (philosophy of mind in particular) and theology, and its emphasis on the laboratory-based experimental method. As part of this development, the psychology of religion emerged as a new approach to studying religious experience, with the US being the major centre of research in this field.[2]

A few years earlier Edwin Diller Starbuck had written a book entitled Psychology of Religion which James had written a preface to. James thanks Starbuck in the preface to his book for having "made over to me his large collection of manuscript material" before then citing Starbucks work throughout The Varieties.[3] [4] Starbuck recollects that James looked through "several hundred" of his documents.[5]

The Varieties was first presented in 1901-2 as a set of twenty Gifford lectures at the University of Edinburgh. This was a lecture series instituted by Adam Gifford and intended to have a popular and public audience on the subject of natural theology, or scientific approaches to the study of religion.[6] James had originally planned for the second half of his lectures to be a philosophical assessment of religion but ill health meant that he could only write one lecture on the topic, resulting in a work more descriptive than James had initially anticipated.[7]

Themes

Religious experiences

In the Varieties, James explicitly excludes from his study both theology and religious institutions, choosing to limit his study to direct and immediate religious experiences, which he regarded as the more interesting object of study.[8] Churches, theologies, and institutions are important as vehicles for passing on insights gained by religious experience but, in James's view, they live second-hand off the original experience of the founder.[9] A key distinction in James's treatment of religion is between that of healthy-minded religion and religion of the sick soul; the former is a religion of life's goodness, while the latter cannot overcome the sense of evil in the world.[8] Although James presents this as a value-neutral distinction between different kinds of religious attitudes, he, in fact, regarded the sick-souled religious experience as preferable, and his anonymous source of melancholy experience in lectures VI and VII is, in fact, autobiographical.[10] Following these autobiographical sections, James transitions into two lectures (IX and X) examining religious conversion from a psychological point-of-view, along with its importance in religious history. James considered healthy-mindedness to be America's main contribution to religion, which he saw running from the transcendentalists Ralph Waldo Emerson and Walt Whitman to Mary Baker Eddy's Christian Science. At the extreme, the "healthy-minded" see sickness and evil as an illusion. James considered belief in the "mind cure" to be reasonable when compared to medicine as practiced at the beginning of the twentieth century.[11]

James devotes two lectures to mysticism, and in the lectures, he outlines four markers common to mystical experiences. These are:

He believed that religious experiences can have "morbid origins"[12] in brain pathology and can be irrational, but nevertheless largely positive. Unlike the bad ideas that people have under the influence of, say, fevers or drunkenness, after a religious experience the ideas and insights usually still make sense to the person, and are often valued for the rest of the person's life.[13]

James had relatively little interest in the legitimacy or illegitimacy of religious experiences. Further, despite James' examples being almost exclusively drawn from Christianity, he did not mean to limit his ideas to any single religion. Religious experiences are something that people sometimes have, under certain conditions. In James' description, these experiences are inherently very complex, often life-altering and largely indescribable and unquantifiable through traditional means, yet measurable in the profound changes they have on the individuals that report such experiences.

Pragmatism

Ultimately James made a pragmatic argument for religion, writing that "the uses of religion, its uses to the individual who has it, and the uses of the individual himself to the world, are the best arguments that truth is in it".[14] As an example of this he gives the therapeutic effects of prayer.[15]

Although James did not fully articulate his pragmatic philosophy until the publication of Pragmatism in 1907, the approach to religious belief in the Varieties is influenced by pragmatic philosophy. In his Philosophy and Conclusions lectures, James concludes that religion is overall beneficial to humankind, although acknowledges that this does not establish its truth.[8] While James intended to approach the topic of religious experience from this pragmatist angle, Richard Rorty argues that he ultimately deviated from this methodology in the Varieties. In his lectures on saintliness, the intention is to discover whether the saintly virtues are beneficial for human life: if they are, then, according to pragmatism, that supports their claim to truth. However, James ends up concluding that the value of the saintly virtues is dependent on their origin: given that the saintly virtues are only beneficial if there is an afterlife for which they can prepare us, their value depends on whether they are divinely ordained or the result of human psychology. This is no longer a question of value but of empirical fact. Hence, Rorty argues that James ends up abandoning his own pragmatist philosophy due to his ultimate reliance of empirical evidence.[16]

James remarked on the aesthetic motivation in an individual choosing a religion and praised religion for its aesthetic value. He said that individuals "involuntarily intellectualize their religious experience" and that metaphysical stipulations about the attributes of a deity "enriches our bare piety to carry these exalted and mysterious verbal additions just as it enriches a church to have an organ and old brasses, marbles and frescoes and stained windows".[17]

James considers the possibility of "over-beliefs", beliefs which are not strictly justified by "reason valid universally" but which might understandably be held by educated people nonetheless. They are "buildings-out performed by the intellect into directions of which feeling originally supplied the hint". Philosophy may contribute to shaping these over-beliefs—for example, traditional arguments for the existence of God, including the cosmological, design, and moral arguments, along with the argument from popular consensus.[18] [19] [20] Although James did not himself endorse any of these arguments: "The fact is that these arguments do but follow the combined suggestions of the facts and of our feeling. They prove nothing rigorously. They only corroborate our pre-existent partialities".[21] He says that individuals in the past had sought such universal proofs, asking "what more ideal refuge could there be than such a system would offer to spirits vexed by the muddiness and accidentality of the world of sensible things?".[22] James says he has his own over-belief, which he does not intend to prove, that there is a greater reality not normally accessible by our normal ways of relating to the world, but which religious experiences can connect us to.[8]

Reception

The August 1902 New York Times review of the first edition ends with the following:

A July 1963 Time magazine review of an expanded edition published that year ends with quotes about the book from Peirce and Santayana:[23]

In 1986, Nicholas Lash criticised James's Varieties, challenging James's separation of the personal and institutional. Lash argues that religious geniuses such as St. Paul or Jesus, with whom James was particularly interested, did not have their religious experiences in isolation but within and influenced by a social and historical context.[24] Ultimately, Lash argues that this comes from James's failure to overcome Cartesian dualism in his thought: while James believed he had succeeded in surpassing Descartes, he was still tied to a notion of an internal ego, distinct from the body or outside world, which undergoes experiences.[25]

The book was cherished by Ludwig Wittgenstein who wrote to Bertrand Russell that "Whenever I have time now I read James’ Varieties of Religious Exp[erience]. This book does me a lot of good".[26] It was one of the few books he recommended to his friend Maurice O'Connor Drury.[27] The influence of James' book is seen from letters sent to him from his sister Hermione as he was serving at the front during World War 1. She was concerned about his well-being and wrote to him that "there will be time for you to be a Jamesian type after the war is over!". Brian McGuinness writes that Wittgenstein aspired to be the 'saintly' type described in the book.[28]

See also

External links

Notes and References

  1. Book: Poole, Randall A . William James in the Moscow Psychological Society . William James in Russian Culture . Joan DeLaney . Grossman . Ruth . Rischin. 2003. Lexington Books . Lanham MD. 978-0739105269. 143.
  2. Book: Taves . Ann . Fits, Trances, and Visions: Experiencing Religion and Explaining Experience from Wesley to James . 1999 . Princeton University Press . Princeton . 261-262.
  3. White . Christopher . A Measured Faith: Edwin Starbuck, William James, and the Scientific Reform of Religious Experience . The Harvard Theological Review . 101 . 3/4 . 431-450.
  4. Book: James . William . The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature . 1917 . . vi.
  5. Book: Edwin Diller Starbuck . Ferm . Vergilius . Religion in Transition . 1937 . 224 . Religion's Use of Me.
  6. Book: Bradley . Matthew . James . William . The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature . 2012 . Oxford University Press . Oxford . x . Introduction. Matthew Bradley.
  7. Book: Niebuhr . Richard . Putnam . Ruth Anna . The Cambridge Companion to William James . 1997 . Cambridge University Press . Cambridge . 216 . William James on Religious Experience.
  8. Web site: William James . Goodman . Russell . 2017 . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . 2019-12-01.
  9. Book: Taylor, Charles . Varieties of Religion Today: William James Revisited . limited . Harvard University Press . 2003 . Cambridge, MA. . 23.
  10. Book: Taylor, Charles . Varieties of Religion Today: William James Revisited . limited . Harvard University Press . 2003 . Cambridge, MA. . Charles Taylor (philosopher) . 33–34.
  11. Duclow. Donald F.. 2002-01-01. William James, Mind-Cure, and the Religion of Healthy-Mindedness. 27511579. Journal of Religion and Health. 41. 1. 45–56. 10.1023/A:1015106105669. 34501644.
  12. Book: Fuller, Andrew Reid. Psychology and Religion: Eight Points of View. 1994-01-01. Rowman & Littlefield. 9780822630364. en.
  13. Book: James, William. The Varieties of Religious Experience. feverish%20fancies.. 1985-01-01. Harvard University Press. 9780674932258. en.
  14. Book: The American Pragmatists . 2013 . OUP . 69.
  15. Book: Clark . Stephanie . Compelling God Theories of Prayer in Anglo-Saxon England . 2018 . University of Toronto Press . 13.
  16. Book: Rorty, Richard . Proudfoot . Wayne . 2004 . William James and a Science of Religions: Reexperiencing The Varieties of Religious Experience . limited . New York . Columbia University Press . 86–97 (95) . Richard Rorty . Some Inconsistencies in James's Varieties. 9780231132046 .
  17. Book: James . William . The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature . 1917 . . 459.
  18. Book: James . William . The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature . 1917 . . 436.
  19. Book: Pragmatism and Religion Classical Sources and Original Essays . 2003 . University of Illinois . 67.
  20. Web site: William James (1842—1910) . Pomerleau . Wayne P. . Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy . 2019-12-02.
  21. Book: James . William . The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature . 1917 . . 439.
  22. Book: James . William . The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature . 1917 . . 434.
  23. Web site: Books: The Waterspouts of God . https://archive.today/20130204172637/http://www.time.com/time/printout/0,8816,896918,00.html . dead . February 4, 2013 . . July 19, 1963. 2010-05-20.
  24. Book: Lash, Nicholas . Easter in Ordinary: Reflections on Human Experience and the Knowledge of God . University Press of Virginia . 1986 . Charlottesville . 54–57.
  25. Book: Lash, Nicholas . Easter in Ordinary: Reflections on Human Experience and the Knowledge of God . University Press of Virginia . 1986 . Charlottesville . 60–64.
  26. Peters . Michael A. . Wittgenstein, mysticism and the ‘religious point of view’: ‘Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent’ . Educational Philosophy and Theory . 2022 . 54 . 12.
  27. Goodman . Russell B. . What Wittgenstein Learned from William James . History of Philosophy Quarterly . 1994 . 11 . 3 . 339-354.
  28. Book: McGuinness . Brian . Wittgenstein's Family Letters: Corresponding with Ludwig . 2020 . Bloomsbury Publishing . 12.