Utilitarianism Explained

In ethical philosophy, utilitarianism is a family of normative ethical theories that prescribe actions that maximize happiness and well-being for the affected individuals.[1] [2] In other words, utilitarian ideas encourage actions that ensure the greatest good for the greatest number. Although different varieties of utilitarianism admit different characterizations, the basic idea behind all of them is, in some sense, to maximize utility, which is often defined in terms of well-being or related concepts. For instance, Jeremy Bentham, the founder of utilitarianism, described utility as the capacity of actions or objects to produce benefits, such as pleasure, happiness, and good, or to prevent harm, such as pain and unhappiness, to those affected.

Utilitarianism is a version of consequentialism, which states that the consequences of any action are the only standard of right and wrong. Unlike other forms of consequentialism, such as egoism and altruism, utilitarianism considers either the interests of all humanity and/or all sentient beings equally. Proponents of utilitarianism have disagreed on a number of issues, such as whether actions should be chosen based on their likely results (act utilitarianism), or whether agents should conform to rules that maximize utility (rule utilitarianism). There is also disagreement as to whether total utility (total utilitarianism) or average utility (average utilitarianism) should be maximized.

The seeds of the theory can be found in the hedonists Aristippus and Epicurus who viewed happiness as the only good, the consequentialism of the ancient Chinese philosopher Mozi who developed a theory to maximize benefit and minimize harm, and in the work of the medieval Indian philosopher Shantideva. The tradition of modern utilitarianism began with Jeremy Bentham, and continued with such philosophers as John Stuart Mill, Henry Sidgwick, R. M. Hare, and Peter Singer. The concept has been applied towards social welfare economics, questions of justice, the crisis of global poverty, the ethics of raising animals for food, and the importance of avoiding existential risks to humanity.

Etymology

Benthamism, the utilitarian philosophy founded by Jeremy Bentham, was substantially modified by his successor John Stuart Mill, who popularized the term utilitarianism.[3] In 1861, Mill acknowledged in a footnote that, though Bentham believed "himself to be the first person who brought the word 'utilitarian' into use, he did not invent it. Rather, he adopted it from a passing expression" in John Galt's 1821 novel Annals of the Parish.[4] However, Mill seems to have been unaware that Bentham had used the term utilitarian in his 1781 letter to George Wilson and his 1802 letter to Étienne Dumont.[3]

Historical background

Pre-modern formulations

See also: State consequentialism. The importance of happiness as an end for humans has long been argued. Forms of hedonism were put forward by the ancient Greek philosophers Aristippus and Epicurus. Aristotle argued that eudaimonia is the highest human good. Augustine wrote that "all men agree in desiring the last end, which is happiness". The idea that conduct should to be judged by its consequences also existed within the ancient world. Consequentialist theories were first developed by the ancient Chinese philosopher Mozi, who proposed a system that sought to maximize benefit and eliminate harm.[5] Mohist consequentialism advocated communitarian moral goods, including political stability, population growth, and wealth, but did not support the utilitarian notion of maximizing individual happiness.[6] Utilitarian ideas can also be found in the work of medieval philosophers. In medieval India, the 8th-century Indian philosopher Śāntideva wrote that we ought "to stop all the present and future pain and suffering of all sentient beings, and to bring about all present and future pleasure and happiness."[7] In medieval Europe, happiness was explored in depth by Thomas Aquinas, in his Summa Theologica.[8] [9] [10] [11] [12] During the Renaissance, consequentialist ideas are present in the work of political philosophy of Niccolò Machiavelli.

18th century

Utilitarianism as a distinct ethical position only emerged in the 18th century, and although it is usually thought to have begun with Jeremy Bentham, there were earlier writers who presented theories that were strikingly similar.

Hutcheson

Francis Hutcheson first introduced a key utilitarian phrase in An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1725): when choosing the most moral action, the amount of virtue in a particular action is proportionate to the number of people it brings happiness to.[13] In the same way, moral evil, or vice, is proportionate to the number of people made to suffer. The best action is the one that procures the greatest happiness of the greatest numbers, and the worst is the one that causes the most misery. In the first three editions of the book, Hutcheson included various mathematical algorithms "to compute the Morality of any Actions." In doing so, he pre-figured the hedonic calculus of Bentham.

John Gay

Some claim that John Gay developed the first systematic theory of utilitarian ethics.[14] In Concerning the Fundamental Principle of Virtue or Morality (1731), Gay argues that:[15]

This pursuit of happiness is given a theological basis:[16]

Hume

In An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (1751), David Hume writes:[17]

Paley

Gay's theological utilitarianism was developed and popularized by William Paley. It has been claimed that Paley was not a very original thinker and that the philosophies in his treatise on ethics is "an assemblage of ideas developed by others and is presented to be learned by students rather than debated by colleagues."[18] Nevertheless, his book The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy (1785) was a required text at Cambridge and Smith (1954) says that Paley's writings were "once as well known in American colleges as were the readers and spellers of William McGuffey and Noah Webster in the elementary schools."[19] Schneewind (1977) writes that "utilitarianism first became widely known in England through the work of William Paley."[20]

The now-forgotten significance of Paley can be judged from the title of Thomas Rawson Birks's 1874 work Modern Utilitarianism or the Systems of Paley, Bentham and Mill Examined and Compared.

Apart from restating that happiness as an end is grounded in the nature of God, Paley also discusses the place of rules, writing:[21]

Classical utilitarianism

Jeremy Bentham

Bentham's book An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation was printed in 1780 but not published until 1789. It is possible that Bentham was spurred on to publish after he saw the success of Paley's Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy.[22] Though Bentham's book was not an immediate success,[23] his ideas were spread further when Pierre Étienne Louis Dumont translated edited selections from a variety of Bentham's manuscripts into French. was published in 1802 and then later retranslated back into English by Hildreth as The Theory of Legislation, although by this time significant portions of Dumont's work had already been retranslated and incorporated into Sir John Bowring's edition of Bentham's works, which was issued in parts between 1838 and 1843.

Perhaps aware that Francis Hutcheson eventually removed his algorithms for calculating the greatest happiness because they "appear'd useless, and were disagreeable to some readers,"[24] Bentham contends that there is nothing novel or unwarranted about his method, for "in all this there is nothing but what the practice of mankind, wheresoever they have a clear view of their own interest, is perfectly conformable to."

Rosen (2003) warns that descriptions of utilitarianism can bear "little resemblance historically to utilitarians like Bentham and J. S. Mill" and can be more "a crude version of act utilitarianism conceived in the twentieth century as a straw man to be attacked and rejected."[25] It is a mistake to think that Bentham is not concerned with rules. His seminal work is concerned with the principles of legislation and the hedonic calculus is introduced with the words "Pleasures then, and the avoidance of pains, are the ends that the legislator has in view." In Chapter VII, Bentham says: "The business of government is to promote the happiness of the society, by punishing and rewarding.... In proportion as an act tends to disturb that happiness, in proportion as the tendency of it is pernicious, will be the demand it creates for punishment."

Principle of utility

Bentham's work opens with a statement of the principle of utility:[26]

Hedonic calculus

In Chapter IV, Bentham introduces a method of calculating the value of pleasures and pains, which has come to be known as the hedonic calculus. Bentham says that the value of a pleasure or pain, considered by itself, can be measured according to its intensity, duration, certainty/uncertainty and propinquity/remoteness. In addition, it is necessary to consider "the tendency of any act by which it is produced" and, therefore, to take account of the act's fecundity, or the chance it has of being followed by sensations of the same kind and its purity, or the chance it has of not being followed by sensations of the opposite kind. Finally, it is necessary to consider the extent, or the number of people affected by the action.

Evils of the first and second order

The question then arises as to when, if at all, it might be legitimate to break the law. This is considered in The Theory of Legislation, where Bentham distinguishes between evils of the first and second order. Those of the first order are the more immediate consequences; those of the second are when the consequences spread through the community causing "alarm" and "danger".

It is true there are cases in which, if we confine ourselves to the effects of the first order, the good will have an incontestable preponderance over the evil. Were the offence considered only under this point of view, it would not be easy to assign any good reasons to justify the rigour of the laws. Every thing depends upon the evil of the second order; it is this which gives to such actions the character of crime, and which makes punishment necessary. Let us take, for example, the physical desire of satisfying hunger. Let a beggar, pressed by hunger, steal from a rich man's house a loaf, which perhaps saves him from starving, can it be possible to compare the good which the thief acquires for himself, with the evil which the rich man suffers?... It is not on account of the evil of the first order that it is necessary to erect these actions into offences, but on account of the evil of the second order.[27]

John Stuart Mill

Mill was brought up as a Benthamite with the explicit intention that he would carry on the cause of utilitarianism.[28] Mill's book Utilitarianism first appeared as a series of three articles published in Fraser's Magazine in 1861 and was reprinted as a single book in 1863.[29] [30]

Higher and lower pleasures

Mill rejects a purely quantitative measurement of utility and says:[31]

The word utility is used to mean general well-being or happiness, and Mill's view is that utility is the consequence of a good action. Utility, within the context of utilitarianism, refers to people performing actions for social utility. With social utility, he means the well-being of many people. Mill's explanation of the concept of utility in his work, Utilitarianism, is that people really do desire happiness, and since each individual desires their own happiness, it must follow that all of us desire the happiness of everyone, contributing to a larger social utility. Thus, an action that results in the greatest pleasure for the utility of society is the best action, or as Jeremy Bentham, the founder of early Utilitarianism put it, as the greatest happiness of the greatest number.

Mill not only viewed actions as a core part of utility, but as the directive rule of moral human conduct. The rule being that we should only be committing actions that provide pleasure to society. This view of pleasure was hedonistic, as it pursued the thought that pleasure is the highest good in life. This concept was adopted by Bentham and can be seen in his works. According to Mill, good actions result in pleasure, and that there is no higher end than pleasure. Mill says that good actions lead to pleasure and define good character. Better put, the justification of character, and whether an action is good or not, is based on how the person contributes to the concept of social utility. In the long run the best proof of a good character is good actions; and resolutely refuse to consider any mental disposition as good, of which the predominant tendency is to produce bad conduct. In the last chapter of Utilitarianism, Mill concludes that justice, as a classifying factor of our actions (being just or unjust) is one of the certain moral requirements, and when the requirements are all regarded collectively, they are viewed as greater according to this scale of "social utility" as Mill puts it.

He also notes that, contrary to what its critics might say, there is "no known Epicurean theory of life which does not assign to the pleasures of the intellect ... a much higher value as pleasures than to those of mere sensation." However, he accepts that this is usually because the intellectual pleasures are thought to have circumstantial advantages, i.e. "greater permanency, safety, uncostliness, &c." Instead, Mill will argue that some pleasures are intrinsically better than others.

The accusation that hedonism is a "doctrine worthy only of swine" has a long history. In Nicomachean Ethics (Book 1 Chapter 5), Aristotle says that identifying the good with pleasure is to prefer a life suitable for beasts. The theological utilitarians had the option of grounding their pursuit of happiness in the will of God; the hedonistic utilitarians needed a different defence. Mill's approach is to argue that the pleasures of the intellect are intrinsically superior to physical pleasures.

Few human creatures would consent to be changed into any of the lower animals, for a promise of the fullest allowance of a beast's pleasures; no intelligent human being would consent to be a fool, no instructed person would be an ignoramus, no person of feeling and conscience would be selfish and base, even though they should be persuaded that the fool, the dunce, or the rascal is better satisfied with his lot than they are with theirs. ... A being of higher faculties requires more to make him happy, is capable probably of more acute suffering, and certainly accessible to it at more points, than one of an inferior type; but in spite of these liabilities, he can never really wish to sink into what he feels to be a lower grade of existence. ... It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. And if the fool, or the pig, are of a different opinion, it is because they only know their own side of the question...[32]

Mill argues that if people who are "competently acquainted" with two pleasures show a decided preference for one even if it be accompanied by more discontent and "would not resign it for any quantity of the other," then it is legitimate to regard that pleasure as being superior in quality. Mill recognizes that these "competent judges" will not always agree, and states that, in cases of disagreement, the judgment of the majority is to be accepted as final. Mill also acknowledges that "many who are capable of the higher pleasures, occasionally, under the influence of temptation, postpone them to the lower. But this is quite compatible with a full appreciation of the intrinsic superiority of the higher." Mill says that this appeal to those who have experienced the relevant pleasures is no different from what must happen when assessing the quantity of pleasure, for there is no other way of measuring "the acutest of two pains, or the intensest of two pleasurable sensations." "It is indisputable that the being whose capacities of enjoyment are low, has the greatest chance of having them fully satisfied; and a highly-endowed being will always feel that any happiness which he can look for, as the world is constitute, is imperfect."[33]

Mill also thinks that "intellectual pursuits have value out of proportion to the amount of contentment or pleasure (the mental state) that they produce."[34] Mill also says that people should pursue these grand ideals, because if they choose to have gratification from petty pleasures, "some displeasure will eventually creep in. We will become bored and depressed."[35] Mill claims that gratification from petty pleasures only gives short-term happiness and, subsequently, worsens the individual who may feel that his life lacks happiness, since the happiness is transient. Whereas, intellectual pursuits give long-term happiness because they provide the individual with constant opportunities throughout the years to improve his life, by benefiting from accruing knowledge. Mill views intellectual pursuits as "capable of incorporating the 'finer things' in life" while petty pursuits do not achieve this goal.[36] Mill is saying that intellectual pursuits give the individual the opportunity to escape the constant depression cycle since these pursuits allow them to achieve their ideals, while petty pleasures do not offer this. Although debate persists about the nature of Mill's view of gratification, this suggests bifurcation in his position.

'Proving' the principle of utility

In Chapter Four of Utilitarianism, Mill considers what proof can be given for the principle of utility:[37]

It is usual to say that Mill is committing a number of fallacies:[38]

Such allegations began to emerge in Mill's lifetime, shortly after the publication of Utilitarianism, and persisted for well over a century, though the tide has been turning in recent discussions. Nonetheless, a defence of Mill against all three charges, with a chapter devoted to each, can be found in Necip Fikri Alican's Mill's Principle of Utility: A Defense of John Stuart Mill's Notorious Proof (1994). This is the first, and remains the only, book-length treatment of the subject matter. Yet the alleged fallacies in the proof continue to attract scholarly attention in journal articles and book chapters.

Hall (1949) and Popkin (1950) defend Mill against this accusation pointing out that he begins Chapter Four by asserting that "questions of ultimate ends do not admit of proof, in the ordinary acceptation of the term" and that this is "common to all first principles".[39] [38] Therefore, according to Hall and Popkin, Mill does not attempt to "establish that what people do desire is desirable but merely attempts to make the principles acceptable." The type of "proof" Mill is offering "consists only of some considerations which, Mill thought, might induce an honest and reasonable man to accept utilitarianism."

Having claimed that people do, in fact, desire happiness, Mill now has to show that it is the only thing they desire. Mill anticipates the objection that people desire other things such as virtue. He argues that whilst people might start desiring virtue as a means to happiness, eventually, it becomes part of someone's happiness and is then desired as an end in itself.

Henry Sidgwick

See main article: Henry Sidgwick. Sidgwick's book The Methods of Ethics has been referred to as the peak or culmination of classical utilitarianism.[40] [41] His main goal in this book is to ground utilitarianism in the principles of common-sense morality and thereby dispense with the doubts of his predecessors that these two are at odds with each other.[41] For Sidgwick, ethics is about which actions are objectively right.[40] Our knowledge of right and wrong arises from common-sense morality, which lacks a coherent principle at its core.[42] The task of philosophy in general and ethics in particular is not so much to create new knowledge but to systematize existing knowledge.[43] Sidgwick tries to achieve this by formulating methods of ethics, which he defines as rational procedures "for determining right conduct in any particular case".[41] He identifies three methods: intuitionism, which involves various independently valid moral principles to determine what ought to be done, and two forms of hedonism, in which rightness only depends on the pleasure and pain following from the action. Hedonism is subdivided into egoistic hedonism, which only takes the agent's own well-being into account, and universal hedonism or utilitarianism, which is concerned with everyone's well-being.[43] [41]

Intuitionism holds that we have intuitive, i.e. non-inferential, knowledge of moral principles, which are self-evident to the knower.[43] The criteria for this type of knowledge include that they are expressed in clear terms, that the different principles are mutually consistent with each other and that there is expert consensus on them. According to Sidgwick, commonsense moral principles fail to pass this test, but there are some more abstract principles that pass it, like that "what is right for me must be right for all persons in precisely similar circumstances" or that "one should be equally concerned with all temporal parts of one's life".[41] [43] The most general principles arrived at this way are all compatible with utilitarianism, which is why Sidgwick sees a harmony between intuitionism and utilitarianism.[44] There are also less general intuitive principles, like the duty to keep one's promises or to be just, but these principles are not universal and there are cases where different duties stand in conflict with each other. Sidgwick suggests that we resolve such conflicts in a utilitarian fashion by considering the consequences of the conflicting actions.[41] [45]

The harmony between intuitionism and utilitarianism is a partial success in Sidgwick's overall project, but he sees full success impossible since egoism, which he considers as equally rational, cannot be reconciled with utilitarianism unless religious assumptions are introduced.[41] Such assumptions, for example, the existence of a personal God who rewards and punishes the agent in the afterlife, could reconcile egoism and utilitarianism.[43] But without them, we have to admit a "dualism of practical reason" that constitutes a "fundamental contradiction" in our moral consciousness.[40]

Developments in the 20th century

Ideal utilitarianism

The description of ideal utilitarianism was first used by Hastings Rashdall in The Theory of Good and Evil (1907), but it is more often associated with G. E. Moore. In Ethics (1912), Moore rejects a purely hedonistic utilitarianism and argues that there is a range of values that might be maximized. Moore's strategy was to show that it is intuitively implausible that pleasure is the sole measure of what is good. He says that such an assumption:[46]

Moore admits that it is impossible to prove the case either way, but he believed that it was intuitively obvious that even if the amount of pleasure stayed the same a world that contained such things as beauty and love would be a better world. He adds that, if a person was to take the contrary view, then "I think it is self-evident that he would be wrong."[46]

Act and rule utilitarianism

See main article: Act utilitarianism and Rule utilitarianism. In the mid-20th century, a number of philosophers focused on the place of rules in utilitarian thought.[47] It was already considered necessary to use rules to help choose the right action, because estimating the consequences every time seemed error-prone and unlikely to bring the best outcome. Paley had justified the use of rules and Mill says:[48]

However, rule utilitarianism proposes a more central role for rules that was thought to rescue the theory from some of its more devastating criticisms, particularly problems to do with justice and promise keeping. Smart (1956) and McCloskey (1957) initially use the terms extreme and restricted utilitarianism but eventually settled on the prefixes act and rule instead.[49] [50] Likewise, throughout the 1950s and 1960s, articles were published both for and against the new form of utilitarianism, and through this debate the theory we now call rule utilitarianism was created. In an introduction to an anthology of these articles, the editor was able to say: "The development of this theory was a dialectical process of formulation, criticism, reply and reformulation; the record of this process well illustrates the co-operative development of a philosophical theory."

The essential difference is in what determines whether or not an action is the right action. Act utilitarianism maintains that an action is right if it maximizes utility; rule utilitarianism maintains that an action is right if it conforms to a rule that maximizes utility.

In 1956, Urmson (1953) published an influential article arguing that Mill justified rules on utilitarian principles.[51] From then on, articles have debated this interpretation of Mill. In all probability, it was not a distinction that Mill was particularly trying to make and so the evidence in his writing is inevitably mixed. A collection of Mill's writing published in 1977 includes a letter that seems to tip the balance in favour of the notion that Mill is best classified as an act utilitarian. In the letter, Mill says:[52]

Some school level textbooks and at least one British examination board make a further distinction between strong and weak rule utilitarianism.[53] However, it is not clear that this distinction is made in the academic literature. It has been argued that rule utilitarianism collapses into act utilitarianism, because for any given rule, in the case where breaking the rule produces more utility, the rule can be refined by the addition of a sub-rule that handles cases like the exception.[54] This process holds for all cases of exceptions, and so the "rules" have as many "sub-rules" as there are exceptional cases, which, in the end, makes an agent seek out whatever outcome produces the maximum utility.[55]

Two-level utilitarianism

See main article: Two-level utilitarianism. In Principles (1973), R. M. Hare accepts that rule utilitarianism collapses into act utilitarianism but claims that this is a result of allowing the rules to be "as specific and un-general as we please."[56] He argues that one of the main reasons for introducing rule utilitarianism was to do justice to the general rules that people need for moral education and character development and he proposes that "a difference between act-utilitarianism and rule-utilitarianism can be introduced by limiting the specificity of the rules, i.e., by increasing their generality."[56] This distinction between a "specific rule utilitarianism" (which collapses into act utilitarianism) and "general rule utilitarianism" forms the basis of Hare's two-level utilitarianism.

When we are "playing God or the ideal observer", we use the specific form, and we will need to do this when we are deciding what general principles to teach and follow. When we are "inculcating" or in situations where the biases of our human nature are likely to prevent us doing the calculations properly, then we should use the more general rule utilitarianism.

Hare argues that in practice, most of the time, we should be following the general principles:[56]

In Moral Thinking (1981), Hare illustrated the two extremes. The "archangel" is the hypothetical person who has perfect knowledge of the situation and no personal biases or weaknesses and always uses critical moral thinking to decide the right thing to do. In contrast, the "prole" is the hypothetical person who is completely incapable of critical thinking and uses nothing but intuitive moral thinking and, of necessity, has to follow the general moral rules they have been taught or learned through imitation.[57] It is not that some people are archangels and others proles, but rather that "we all share the characteristics of both to limited and varying degrees and at different times."[57]

Hare does not specify when we should think more like an "archangel" and more like a "prole" as this will, in any case, vary from person to person. However, the critical moral thinking underpins and informs the more intuitive moral thinking. It is responsible for formulating and, if necessary, reformulating the general moral rules. We also switch to critical thinking when trying to deal with unusual situations or in cases where the intuitive moral rules give conflicting advice.

Preference utilitarianism

See main article: Preference utilitarianism. Preference utilitarianism entails promoting actions that fulfil the preferences of those beings involved.[58] The concept of preference utilitarianism was first proposed in 1977 by John Harsanyi in Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour,[59] [60] however the concept is more commonly associated with R. M. Hare,[57] Peter Singer,[61] and Richard Brandt.[62]

Harsanyi claims that his theory is indebted to:[60]

Harsanyi rejects hedonistic utilitarianism as being dependent on an outdated psychology saying that it is far from obvious that everything we do is motivated by a desire to maximize pleasure and minimize pain. He also rejects ideal utilitarianism because "it is certainly not true as an empirical observation that people's only purpose in life is to have 'mental states of intrinsic worth'."

According to Harsanyi, "preference utilitarianism is the only form of utilitarianism consistent with the important philosophical principle of preference autonomy. By this I mean the principle that, in deciding what is good and what is bad for a given individual, the ultimate criterion can only be his own wants and his own preferences."[60]

Harsanyi adds two caveats. Firstly, people sometimes have irrational preferences. To deal with this, Harsanyi distinguishes between "manifest" preferences and "true" preferences. The former are those "manifested by his observed behaviour, including preferences possibly based on erroneous factual beliefs, or on careless logical analysis, or on strong emotions that at the moment greatly hinder rational choice"; whereas the latter are "the preferences he would have if he had all the relevant factual information, always reasoned with the greatest possible care, and were in a state of mind most conducive to rational choice."[60] It is the latter that preference utilitarianism tries to satisfy.

The second caveat is that antisocial preferences, such as sadism, envy, and resentment, have to be excluded. Harsanyi achieves this by claiming that such preferences partially exclude those people from the moral community:

Negative utilitarianism

See main article: Negative utilitarianism. In The Open Society and its Enemies (1945), Karl Popper argues that the principle "maximize pleasure" should be replaced by "minimize pain". He believes that "it is not only impossible but very dangerous to attempt to maximize the pleasure or the happiness of the people, since such an attempt must lead to totalitarianism."[63] He claims that:[64]

The actual term negative utilitarianism itself was introduced by R. N. Smart as the title to his 1958 reply to Popper in which he argues that the principle would entail seeking the quickest and least painful method of killing the entirety of humanity.[65]

In response to Smart's argument, Simon Knutsson (2019) has argued that classical utilitarianism and similar consequentialist views are roughly equally likely to entail killing the entirety of humanity, as they would seem to imply that one should kill existing beings and replace them with happier beings if possible. Consequently, Knutsson argues:

Furthermore, Knutsson notes that one could argue that other forms of consequentialism, such as classical utilitarianism, in some cases have less plausible implications than negative utilitarianism, such as in scenarios where classical utilitarianism implies it would be right to kill everyone and replace them in a manner that creates more suffering, but also more well-being such that the sum, on the classical utilitarian calculus, is net positive. Negative utilitarianism, in contrast, would not allow such killing.[66]

Some versions of negative utilitarianism include:

Notes and References

  1. Duignan, Brian. [1999] 2000. "Utilitarianism" (revised). Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 5 July 2020.
  2. Web site: Utilitarianism. 2020-05-27. Ethics Unwrapped. McCombs School of Business. Austin, TX. en-US.
  3. Book: Habibi, Don . Mill's Moral Philosophy . John Stuart Mill and the Ethic of Human Growth . Springer Netherlands . Dordrecht . 2001 . 978-90-481-5668-9 . 89–90, 112. 10.1007/978-94-017-2010-6_3 .
  4. [John Stuart Mill|Mill, John Stuart]
  5. Book: Fraser. Chris. The Philosophy of the Mòzĭ: The First Consequentialists. 2016. Columbia University Press. 978-0-23-152059-1. 138.
  6. Book: Fraser. Chris. The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy. 2011. Oxford University Press. 978-0-19-532899-8. 62.
  7. Goodman, Charles. 2016. "Śāntideva", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 31 August 2020.
  8. Web site: SUMMA THEOLOGICA: Man's last end (Prima Secundae Partis, Q. 1). newadvent.org.
  9. Web site: SUMMA THEOLOGICA: Things in which man's happiness consists (Prima Secundae Partis, Q. 2). newadvent.org.
  10. Web site: SUMMA THtheEOLOGICA: What is happiness (Prima Secundae Partis, Q. 3). newadvent.org.
  11. Web site: SUMMA THEOLOGICA: Things that are required for happiness (Prima Secundae Partis, Q. 4). newadvent.org.
  12. Web site: SUMMA THEOLOGICA: The attainment of happiness (Prima Secundae Partis, Q. 5). newadvent.org.
  13. Book: Hutcheson, Francis. Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant. Cambridge University Press. 2002. 978-0-521-00304-9. Schneewind. J. B.. 515. The Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue. 1725.
  14. Ashcraft, Richard (1991) John Locke: Critical Assessments (Critical assessments of leading political philosophers), Routledge, p. 691
  15. Book: Gay, John . J. B. . Schneewind . Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant . Cambridge University Press . 2002 . 408 . Concerning the Fundamental Principle of Virtue or Morality . 978-0-521-00304-9.
  16. Book: Gay, John . J. B. . Schneewind . Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant . Cambridge University Press . 2002 . 404–05 . Concerning the Fundamental Principle of Virtue or Morality . 978-0-521-00304-9.
  17. Book: Hume, David. Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant. Cambridge University Press. 2002. 978-0-521-00304-9. Schneewind. J. B.. 552. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals.
  18. Book: Schneewind, J. B. . Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant . Cambridge University Press . 2002 . 446 . 978-0-521-00304-9.
  19. Smith . Wilson . July 1954 . William Paley's Theological Utilitarianism in America . William and Mary Quarterly . 3rd Series . 11 . 3 . 402–24 . 10.2307/1943313. 1943313 .
  20. Book: Schneewind, J. B. . Sidgwick's Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy . Oxford University Press . 1977 . 122 . 978-0-19-824552-0.
  21. Book: Paley, William . J. B. . Schneewind . Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to Kant . Cambridge University Press . 2002 . 455–56 . The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy . 978-0-521-00304-9.
  22. Rosen, Frederick. 2003. Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill. Routledge. p. 132.
  23. Schneewind, J. B. 1977. Sidgwick's Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 122.
  24. [Francis Hutcheson (philosopher)|Hutcheson, Francis.]
  25. Rosen, Frederick. 2003. Classical Utilitarianism from Hume to Mill. Routledge. p. 32.
  26. [Jeremy Bentham|Bentham, Jeremy]
  27. Book: Bentham . Jeremy . Dumont . Etienne . Hildreth . R . Theory of Legislation: Translated from the French of Etienne Dumont . Adamant Media Corporation . November 2005 . 58 . 978-1-4021-7034-8.
  28. Book: Halevy, Elie. The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism. 1966. Beacon Press. 978-0-19-101020-0. 282–84.
  29. Book: Hinman, Lawrence. Ethics: A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory. Wadsworth. 2012. 978-1-133-05001-8.
  30. Book: Mill, John Stuart. 1863. 2010. Utilitarianism - Ed. Heydt (Broadview Editions). 33. 978-1-55111-501-6. Broadview Press . 2019-07-28.
  31. Book: Mill, John Stuart . Roger . Crisp . Utilitarianism . Oxford University Press . 1998 . 56 . 978-0-19-875163-2.
  32. Book: Mill, John Stuart . Roger . Crisp . Utilitarianism . Oxford University Press . 1998 . 56–57 . 978-0-19-875163-2.
  33. John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, Chapter 2
  34. Brink, David. [2007] 2018. "Mill Moral and Political Philosophy." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 5 July 2020.
  35. 10.1017/S0953820811000264. No Philosophy for Swine: John Stuart Mill on the Quality of Pleasures. Utilitas. 23. 4. 428–446. 2011. Hauskeller. Michael. 10871/9381. 170099688. free.
  36. Saunders, Ben. 2010. "J. S. Mill's Conception of Utility." Utilitas 22(1):52–69. . .
  37. Book: Mill, John Stuart . Roger . Crisp . Utilitarianism . Oxford . Oxford University Press . 1998 . 81 . 978-0-19-875163-2.
  38. Popkin. Richard H.. 1950. A Note on the 'Proof' of Utility in J. S. Mill. Ethics. 61. 66–68. 10.1086/290751. 170936711.
  39. Hall. Everett W.. 1949. The 'Proof' of Utility in Bentham and Mill. Ethics. 60. 1–18. 10.1086/290691. 145767787.
  40. Web site: Schultz . Barton . Henry Sidgwick . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University . 29 December 2020 . 2020.
  41. Book: Craig . Edward . Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy . 1996 . Routledge . Sidgwick, Henry.
  42. Web site: Duignan . Brian . West . Henry R. . Utilitarianism . Encyclopedia Britannica . 29 December 2020 . en.
  43. Book: Borchert . Donald M. . Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition . 2006 . Macmillan . Sidgwick, Henry.
  44. Book: Honderich . Ted . The Oxford Companion to Philosophy . 2005 . Oxford University Press . Sidgwick, Henry.
  45. Book: Borchert . Donald M. . Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition . 2006 . Macmillan . Sidgwick, Henry [Addendum].
  46. Moore, G. E. (1912). Ethics, London: Williams and Norgate, Ch. 7
  47. Bayles, M. D., ed. 1968. Contemporary Utilitarianism. Doubleday: Anchor Books.
  48. Book: Mill, John Stuart . Roger . Crisp . Utilitarianism . Oxford University Press . 1998 . 70 . 978-0-19-875163-2.
  49. Smart. J. J. C.. 1956. Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism. Philosophical Quarterly. 6. 25. 344–54. 10.2307/2216786. 2216786. 147501349.
  50. McCloskey. H. J.. October 1957. An Examination of Restricted Utilitarianism. Philosophical Review. 66. 4. 466–85. 10.2307/2182745. 2182745.
  51. Urmson. J. O.. 1953. The Interpretation of the Moral Philosophy of J. S. Mill. Philosophical Quarterly. 3. 10. 33–39. 10.2307/2216697. 2216697.
  52. Mill, John Stuart. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill 17, edited by J. M. Robson. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. 1963–91. p. 1881.
  53. Oliphant, Jill. 2007. OCR Religious Ethics for AS and A2. Routledge.
  54. [David Lyons (philosopher)|Lyons, David]
  55. Habib, Allen. [2008] 2014. "Promises." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  56. Hare. R. M.. R. M. Hare. 1972–1973. The Presidential Address: Principles. . New Series. 73. 1–18. 10.1093/aristotelian/73.1.1. 4544830.
  57. Book: Hare, R.M. . R. M. Hare . Moral thinking: its levels, method, and point . Clarendon Press Oxford University Press . Oxford New York . 1981 . 978-0-19-824660-2 .
  58. Peter Singer, Practical Ethics, 2011, p. 13
  59. [John Harsanyi|Harsanyi, John C.]
  60. [John Harsanyi|Harsanyi, John C.]
  61. Book: Singer, Peter . Peter Singer . Practical ethics . Cambridge University Press . Cambridge New York . 1979 . 1st . 978-0-521-29720-2 .

    Book: Singer, Peter . Peter Singer . Practical ethics . Cambridge University Press . Cambridge/New York . 1993 . 2nd . 978-0-521-43971-8 .

  62. Book: Brandt, Richard B. . Richard Brandt . A Theory of the Good and the Right . Clarendon Press . Oxford/New York . 1979 . 978-0-19-824550-6 .
  63. Book: Popper, Karl. The Open Society and Its Enemies: Volume 2. 2002. Routledge. 978-0-415-27842-3. 339.
  64. Book: Popper, Karl. The Open Society and Its Enemies: Volume 1: The Spell of Plato. 2002. Routledge. 978-0-415-23731-4. 284–85.
  65. Smart. R.N.. October 1958. Negative Utilitarianism. Mind. 67. 268. 542–43. 10.1093/mind/lxvii.268.542. 2251207.
  66. Knutsson. Simon. 2019-08-29. The world destruction argument. Inquiry. 64. 10. 1004–1023. 10.1080/0020174X.2019.1658631. 0020-174X. free.
  67. Fabian, Fricke. 2002. "Verschiedene Versionen des negativen Utilitarismus." Kriterion 15(1): p. 14.
  68. Gustav, Arrhenius. 2000. "Future Generations, A Challenge for Moral Theory" (FD-Diss.). Uppsala: Uppsala University, Department of Philosophy. p. 100.
  69. Fricke Fabian (2002), Verschiedene Versionen des negativen Utilitarismus, Kriterion, vol.15, no.1, pp. 20–22