Indescribable cardinal explained
In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a Q-indescribable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number that is hard to axiomatize in some language Q. There are many different types of indescribable cardinals corresponding to different choices of languages Q. They were introduced by .
A cardinal number
is called
-indescribable if for every
proposition
, and set
with
(V\kappa+n,\in,A)\vDash\phi
there exists an
with
(V\alpha+n,\in,A\capV\alpha)\vDash\phi
.
[1] Following
Lévy's hierarchy, here one looks at formulas with m-1 alternations of quantifiers with the outermost quantifier being universal.
-indescribable cardinals are defined in a similar way, but with an outermost existential quantifier. Prior to defining the structure
, one new predicate symbol is added to the language of set theory, which is interpreted as
.
[2] The idea is that
cannot be distinguished (looking from below) from smaller cardinals by any formula of n+1-th order logic with m-1 alternations of quantifiers even with the advantage of an extra unary predicate symbol (for A). This implies that it is large because it means that there must be many smaller cardinals with similar properties.
The cardinal number
is called
totally indescribable if it is
-indescribable for all positive integers
m and
n.
If
is an ordinal, the cardinal number
is called
-indescribable if for every formula
and every subset
of
such that
holds in
there is a some
such that
holds in
. If
is infinite then
-indescribable ordinals are totally indescribable, and if
is finite they are the same as
-indescribable ordinals. There is no
that is
-indescribable, nor does
-indescribability necessarily imply
-indescribability for any
, but there is an alternative notion of
shrewd cardinals that makes sense when
: if
holds in
, then there are
and
such that
holds in
.
[3] However, it is possible that a cardinal
is
-indescribable for
much greater than
.
Ch. 9, theorem 4.3Historical note
Originally, a cardinal κ was called Q-indescribable if for every Q-formula
and relation
, if
then there exists an
such that
(\alpha,\in,A\upharpoonright\alpha)\vDash\phi
.
[4] [5] Using this definition,
is
-indescribable iff
is regular and greater than
.
p.207 The cardinals
satisfying the above version based on the cumulative hierarchy were called strongly Q-indescribable.
[6] This property has also been referred to as "ordinal
-indescribability".
[7] p.32Equivalent conditions
A cardinal is
-indescribable iff it is
-indescribable.
[8] A cardinal is
inaccessible if and only if it is
-indescribable for all positive integers
, equivalently iff it is
-indescribable, equivalently if it is
-indescribable.
-indescribable cardinals are the same as
weakly compact cardinals.
The indescribability condition is equivalent to
satisfying the
reflection principle (which is provable in ZFC), but extended by allowing higher-order formulae with a second-order free variable.
[8] For cardinals
, say that an elementary embedding
a
small embedding if
is transitive and
. For any natural number
,
is
-indescribable iff there is an
such that for all
there is a small embedding
such that
H(rm{crit}(j)+)
H(rm{crit}(j)+)
.
[9] , Corollary 4.3If V=L, then for a natural number n>0, an uncountable cardinal is Π-indescribable iff it's (n+1)-stationary.[10]
Enforceable classes
For a class
of ordinals and a
-indescribable cardinal
,
is said to be enforced at
(by some formula
of
) if there is a
-formula
and an
such that
(V\kappa,\in,A)\vDash\phi
, but for no
with
does
(V\beta,\in,A\capV\beta)\vDash\phi
hold.
p.277 This gives a tool to show necessary properties of indescribable cardinals.
Properties
The property of
being
-indescribable is
over
, i.e. there is a
sentence that
satisfies iff
is
-indescribable.
[11] For
, the property of being
-indescribable is
and the property of being
-indescribable is
. Thus, for
, every cardinal that is either
-indescribable or
-indescribable is both
-indescribable and
-indescribable and the set of such cardinals below it is stationary. The consistency strength of
-indescribable cardinals is below that of
-indescribable, but for
it is consistent with ZFC that the least
-indescribable exists and is above the least
-indescribable cardinal (this is proved from consistency of ZFC with
-indescribable cardinal and a
-indescribable cardinal above it).
Totally indescribable cardinals remain totally indescribable in the constructible universe and in other canonical inner models, and similarly for
- and
-indescribability.
For natural number
, if a cardinal
is
-indescribable, there is an ordinal
such that
(V\alpha+n,\in)\equiv(V\kappa+n,\in)
, where
denotes
elementary equivalence.
[12] For
this is a biconditional (see Two model-theoretic characterisations of inaccessibility).
Measurable cardinals are
-indescribable, but the smallest measurable cardinal is not
-indescribable. However, assuming
choice, there are many totally indescribable cardinals below any measurable cardinal.
For
, ZFC+"there is a
-indescribable cardinal" is equiconsistent with ZFC+"there is a
-indescribable cardinal
such that
", i.e. "GCH fails at a
-indescribable cardinal".
[8] References
- Book: Kanamori, Akihiro. Akihiro Kanamori. 2003. Springer. The Higher Infinite : Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings. The Higher Infinite. 2nd. 3-540-00384-3. 10.1007/978-3-540-88867-3_2.
Citations
Notes and References
- Book: Drake, F. R.. Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics ; V. 76). Elsevier Science Ltd. 1974. 0-444-10535-2.
- Book: Jech . Thomas. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, revised and expanded. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. 2006. 3-540-44085-2. 10.1007/3-540-44761-X. 295.
- M. Rathjen, "The Higher Infinite in Proof Theory" (1995), p.20. Archived 14 January 2024.
- K. Kunen, "Indescribability and the Continuum" (1971). Appearing in Axiomatic Set Theory: Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. 13 part 1, pp.199--203
- Azriel Lévy, "The Sizes of the Indescribable Cardinals" (1971). Appearing in Axiomatic Set Theory: Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. 13 part 1, pp.205--218
- Richter . Wayne. Aczel . Peter. Inductive Definitions and Reflecting Properties of Admissible Ordinals. 1974. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. 79. 301–381. 10.1016/S0049-237X(08)70592-5. 10852/44063. free.
- W. Boos, "Lectures on large cardinal axioms". In Logic Conference, Kiel 1974. Lecture Notes in Mathematics 499 (1975).
- Hauser . Kai. Indescribable Cardinals and Elementary Embeddings. 2274692. Journal of Symbolic Logic. 56. 2. 1991. 439–457. 10.2307/2274692.
- Holy . Peter. Lücke . Philipp. Njegomir . Ana. Small embedding characterizations for large cardinals. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 170. 2. 2019. 251–271. 10.1016/j.apal.2018.10.002 . free. 1708.06103.
- Bagaria . Joan. Magidor . Menachem . Menachem Magidor. Sakai . Hiroshi. Reflection and indescribability in the constructible universe. Israel Journal of Mathematics. 208. 1–11. 2015. 10.1007/s11856-015-1191-7.
- Book: Kanamori, Akihiro. Akihiro Kanamori. 2003. Springer. The Higher Infinite : Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings. The Higher Infinite. 2nd. 3-540-00384-3. 10.1007/978-3-540-88867-3_2. 64.
- W. N. Reinhardt, "Ackermann's set theory equals ZF", pp.234--235. Annals of Mathematical Logic vol. 2, iss. 2 (1970).