A strongly proportional division (sometimes called super-proportional division) is a kind of a fair division. It is a division of resources among n partners, in which the value received by each partner is strictly more than his/her due share of 1/n of the total value. Formally, in a strongly proportional division of a resource C among n partners, each partner i, with value measure Vi, receives a share Xi such that
Obviously, a strongly proportional division does not exist when all partners have the same value measure. The best condition that can always be guaranteed is.Vi(Xi)>Vi(C)/n
Vi(Xi)\geqVi(C)/n
In 1948, Hugo Steinhaus conjectured the existence of a super-proportional division of a cake:[1]
It may be stated incidentally that if there are two (or more) partners with different estimations, there exists a division giving to everybody more than his due part (Knaster); this fact disproves the common opinion that differences estimations make fair division difficult.In 1961, Dubins and Spanier proved that the necessary condition for existence is also sufficient. That is, whenever the partners' valuations are additive and non-atomic, and there are at least two partners whose value function is even slightly different, then there is a super-proportional division in which all partners receive more than 1/n.
The proof was a corollary to the Dubins–Spanier convexity theorem. This was a purely existential proof based on convexity arguments.
In 1986, Douglas R. Woodall published the first protocol for finding a super-proportional division.[2]
Let C be the entire cake. If the agents' valuations are different, then there must be a witness for that: a witness is a specific piece of cake, say X ⊆ C, which is valued differently by some two partners, say Alice and Bob. Let Y := C \ X. Let ax=VAlice(X) and bx=VBob(X) and ay=VAlice(Y) and by=VBob(Y), and assume w.l.o.g. that:
bx > ax, which implies: by < ay.The idea is to partition X and Y separately: when partitioning X, we will give slightly more to Bob and slightly less to Alice; when partitioning Y, we will give slightly more to Alice and slightly less to Bob.
Find a rational number between bx and ax, say p/q such that bx > p/q > ax. This implies by < (q-p)/q < ay. Ask Bob to divide X into p equal parts, and divide Y to q-p equal parts.
By our assumptions, Bob values each piece of X at bx/p > 1/q, and each piece of Y at by/(q-p) < 1/q. But for Alice, at least one piece of X (say X0) must have value less than 1/q and at least one piece of Y (say Y0) must have value more than 1/q.
So now we have two pieces, X0 and Y0, such that:
VBob(X0)>VAlice(X0)
VBob(Y0)
Now, each partner thinks that his/her allocation is strictly better than the other allocation, so its value is strictly more than 1/2.
The extension of this protocol to n partners is based on Fink's "Lone Chooser" protocol.
Suppose we already have a strongly proportional division to i-1 partners (for i≥3). Now partner #i enters the party and we should give him a small piece from each of the first i-1 partners, such that the new division is still strongly proportional.
Consider e.g. partner #1. Let d be the difference between partner #1's current value and (1/(i-1)). Because the current division is strongly proportional, we know that d>0.
Choose a positive integer q such that:
d>
1 | |
(i-1)i(q(i-1)-1) |
Ask partner #1 to divide his share to
qi-1
q
Partner #1 remains with a value of
(qi-1)-q | |
qi-1 |
=
q(i-1)-1 | |
qi-1 |
1 | |
i-1 |
+d
q(i-1)-1 | |
(i-1)(qi-1) |
1 | |
i(i-1)(qi-1) |
(qi-1)(i-1) | |
(i-1)i(qi-1) |
=
1 | |
i |
As for the new partner, after having taken q pieces from each of the first i-1 partners, his total value is at least:
q | |
qi-1 |
>
1 | |
i |
This proves that the new division is strongly proportional too.
Julius Barbanel[3] extended Woodall's algorithm to agents with different entitlements, including irrational entitlements. In this setting, the entitlement of each agent i is represented by a weight
wi
W:=\sumiwi
.Vi(Xi)>wi ⋅ Vi(C)/W
Janko and Joo[4] presented a simpler algorithm for agents with different entitlements. In fact, they showed how to reduce a problem of strongly proportional division (with equal or different entitlements) into two problems of proportional division with different entitlements:
wA-1/ax
wB+1/bx
wA+wB
wA+1/ay
wB-1/by
& (w_A - 1/a_x)\cdot a_x / W_X + (w_A + 1/b_y)\cdot b_x / W_Y =\\=&(w_A a_x - 1) / W_X + (w_A a_y + 1) / W_Y \\>&(w_A a_x - 1) / W + (w_A a_y + 1) / W\\=&w_A V_A(C) / W\end
& (w_B + 1/b_x)\cdot b_x / W_X + (w_B - 1/b_y)\cdot b_y / W_Y =\\=&(w_B b_x + 1) / W_X + (w_B b_y - 1) / W_Y \\>&(w_B b_x - 1) / W + (w_B b_y + 1) / W\\=&w_B V_B(C) / W\end
& w_i \cdot V_i(X) / W_X + w_i \cdot V_i(Y) / W_Y \\>&w_i \cdot V_i(X) / W + w_i \cdot V_i(Y) / W\\=&w_i V_i(C) / W\endSo the division is strongly proportional.
An allocation is called strongly envy-free if for every two partners i,j:
An allocation is called super envy-free if for every two partners i,j:.Vi(Xi)>Vi(Xj)
Super envy-freeness implies strong envy-freeness, which implies strong proportionality.[5].Vi(Xi)>1/n>Vi(Xj)