Stochastic transitivity explained

Stochastic transitivity models[1] [2] [3] [4] are stochastic versions of the transitivity property of binary relations studied in mathematics. Several models of stochastic transitivity exist and have been used to describe the probabilities involved in experiments of paired comparisons, specifically in scenarios where transitivity is expected, however, empirical observations of the binary relation is probabilistic. For example, players' skills in a sport might be expected to be transitive, i.e. "if player A is better than B and B is better than C, then player A must be better than C"; however, in any given match, a weaker player might still end up winning with a positive probability. Tightly matched players might have a higher chance of observing this inversion while players with large differences in their skills might only see these inversions happen seldom. Stochastic transitivity models formalize such relations between the probabilities (e.g. of an outcome of a match) and the underlying transitive relation (e.g. the skills of the players).

A binary relation \succsim on a set

l{A}

is called transitive, in the standard non-stochastic sense, if

a\succsimb

and

b\succsimc

implies

a\succsimc

for all members

a,b,c

of

l{A}

.

Stochastic versions of transitivity include:

  1. Weak Stochastic Transitivity (WST):

P(a\succsimb)\geq\tfrac{1}{2}

and

P(b\succsimc)\geq\tfrac{1}{2}

implies

P(a\succsimc)\geq\tfrac{1}{2}

, for all

a,b,c\inl{A}

;[5] [6]
  1. Strong Stochastic Transitivity (SST):

P(a\succsimb)\geq\tfrac{1}{2}

and

P(b\succsimc)\geq\tfrac{1}{2}

implies

P(a\succsimc)\geqmax\{P(a\succsimb),P(b\succsimc)\}

, for all

a,b,c\inl{A}

;[5]
  1. Linear Stochastic Transitivity (LST):

P(a\succsimb)=F(\mu(a)-\mu(b))

, for all

a,b\inl{A}

, where

F:R\to[0,1]

is some increasing and function (called a comparison function), and

\mu:l{A}\toR

is some mapping from the set

l{A}

of alternatives to the real line (called a merit function).

A toy example

The marble game - Assume two kids, Billy and Gabriela, collect marbles. Billy collects blue marbles and Gabriela green marbles. When they get together they play a game where they mix all their marbles in a bag and sample one randomly. If the sampled marble is green, then Gabriela wins and if it is blue then Billy wins. If

B

is the number of blue marbles and

G

is the number of green marbles in the bag, then the probability

P(Billy\succsimGabriela)

of Billy winning against Gabriela is

P(Billy\succsimGabriela)=

B
B+G

=

eln(B)
eln(B)+eln(G)

=

1
1+eln(G)-ln(B)
.

In this example, the marble game satisfies linear stochastic transitivity, where the comparison function

F:R\to[0,1]

is given by

F(x)=

1
1+e-x
and the merit function

\mu:l{A}\toR

is given by

\mu(M)=ln(M)

, where

M

is the number of marbles of the player. This game happens to be an example of a Bradley–Terry model.[7]

Applications

Connections between models

Positive Results:

  1. Every model that satisfies Linear Stochastic Transitivity must also satisfy Strong Stochastic Transitivity, which in turn must satisfy Weak Stochastic Transitivity. This is represented as: LST

\implies

SST

\implies

WST ;
  1. Since the Bradley-Terry models and Thurstone's Case V model[8] are LST models, they also satisfy SST and WST;
  2. Due to the convenience of, a few authors[20] [21] have identified axiomatic of linear stochastic transitivity (and other models), most notably Gérard Debreu showed that:[10] +

\implies

LST (see also Debreu Theorems);
  1. Two LST models given by invertible comparison functions

F(x)

and

G(x)

are if and only if

F(x)=G(\kappax)

for some

\kappa\geq0.

[22]

Negative Results:

  1. Stochastic transitivity models are empirically, however, they may be falsifiable;
  2. between LST comparison functions

F(x)

and

G(x)

can be impossible even if an infinite amount of data is provided over a finite number of ;[23]
  1. The for WST, SST and LST models are in general NP-Hard,[24] however, near optimal polynomially computable estimation procedures are known for SST and LST models.

See also

Notes and References

  1. Fishburn. Peter C.. November 1973. Binary choice probabilities: on the varieties of stochastic transitivity. Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 10. 4. 327–352. 10.1016/0022-2496(73)90021-7. 0022-2496.
  2. Clark. Stephen A.. March 1990. A concept of stochastic transitivity for the random utility model. Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 34. 1. 95–108. 10.1016/0022-2496(90)90015-2.
  3. Ryan. Matthew. 2017-01-21. Uncertainty and binary stochastic choice. Economic Theory. 65. 3. 629–662. 10.1007/s00199-017-1033-4. 125420775. 0938-2259.
  4. Oliveira. I.F.D.. Zehavi. S.. Davidov. O.. August 2018. Stochastic transitivity: Axioms and models. Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 85. 25–35. 10.1016/j.jmp.2018.06.002. 0022-2496.
  5. Experimental tests of a stochastic decision theory . Donald Davidson and Jacob Marschak . Stanford University . Technical Report . 17 . Jul 1958 .
  6. Transitivity of Preferences . Michel Regenwetter and Jason Dana and Clintin P. Davis-Stober . Psychological Review . 118 . 1 . 42 - 56 . 2011 . 10.1037/a0021150 . 21244185 .
  7. Bradley. Ralph Allan. Terry. Milton E.. December 1952. Rank Analysis of Incomplete Block Designs: I. The Method of Paired Comparisons. Biometrika. 39. 3/4. 324. 10.2307/2334029. 2334029.
  8. Thurstone. L. L.. 1994. A law of comparative judgment.. Psychological Review. 101. 2. 266–270. 10.1037/0033-295X.101.2.266. 0033-295X.
  9. Book: Luce, R. Duncan (Robert Duncan). Individual choice behavior : a theoretical analysis. 2005. Dover Publications. 0486441369. Mineola, N.Y.. 874031603.
  10. Debreu. Gerard. July 1958. Stochastic Choice and Cardinal Utility. Econometrica. 26. 3. 440–444. 10.2307/1907622. 0012-9682. 1907622.
  11. Regenwetter. Michel. Dana. Jason. Davis-Stober. Clintin P.. 2011. Transitivity of preferences.. Psychological Review. 118. 1. 42–56. 10.1037/a0021150. 21244185. 1939-1471.
  12. Cavagnaro. Daniel R.. Davis-Stober. Clintin P.. 2014. Transitive in our preferences, but transitive in different ways: An analysis of choice variability.. Decision. 1. 2. 102–122. 10.1037/dec0000011. 2325-9973.
  13. Shah. Nihar B.. Balakrishnan. Sivaraman. Guntuboyina. Adityanand. Wainwright. Martin J.. February 2017. Stochastically Transitive Models for Pairwise Comparisons: Statistical and Computational Issues. IEEE Transactions on Information Theory. 63. 2. 934–959. 10.1109/tit.2016.2634418. 0018-9448. free. 1510.05610.
  14. Chatterjee. Sabyasachi. Mukherjee. Sumit. June 2019. Estimation in Tournaments and Graphs Under Monotonicity Constraints. IEEE Transactions on Information Theory. 65. 6. 3525–3539. 10.1109/tit.2019.2893911. 0018-9448. 1603.04556. 54740089.
  15. Oliveira. Ivo F.D.. Ailon. Nir. Davidov. Ori. 2018. A New and Flexible Approach to the Analysis of Paired Comparison Data. Journal of Machine Learning Research. 19. 1–29.
  16. Israel. Robert B.. December 1981. Stronger Players Need not Win More Knockout Tournaments. Journal of the American Statistical Association. 76. 376. 950–951. 10.2307/2287594. 0162-1459. 2287594.
  17. Chen. Robert. Hwang. F. K.. December 1988. Stronger players win more balanced knockout tournaments. Graphs and Combinatorics. 4. 1. 95–99. 10.1007/bf01864157. 44602228. 0911-0119.
  18. Adler. Ilan. Cao. Yang. Karp. Richard. Peköz. Erol A.. Ross. Sheldon M.. December 2017. Random Knockout Tournaments. Operations Research. 65. 6. 1589–1596. 10.1287/opre.2017.1657. 0030-364X. 1612.04448. 1041539.
  19. Sen. Amartya. January 1977. Social Choice Theory: A Re-Examination. Econometrica. 45. 1. 53–89. 10.2307/1913287. 0012-9682. 1913287.
  20. Book: Blavatskyy, Pavlo R.. Stochastic utility theorem. 2007. Inst. for Empirical Research in Economics. 255736997.
  21. Dagsvik. John K.. October 2015. Stochastic models for risky choices: A comparison of different axiomatizations. Journal of Mathematical Economics. 60. 81–88. 10.1016/j.jmateco.2015.06.013. 0304-4068.
  22. Yellott. John I.. April 1977. The relationship between Luce's Choice Axiom, Thurstone's Theory of Comparative Judgment, and the double exponential distribution. Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 15. 2. 109–144. 10.1016/0022-2496(77)90026-8. 0022-2496.
  23. Rockwell. Christina. Yellott. John I.. February 1979. A note on equivalent Thurstone models. Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 19. 1. 65–71. 10.1016/0022-2496(79)90006-3. 0022-2496.
  24. deCani. John S.. December 1969. Maximum Likelihood Paired Comparison Ranking by Linear Programming. Biometrika. 56. 3. 537–545. 10.2307/2334661. 0006-3444. 2334661.