Stochastic ordering explained

In probability theory and statistics, a stochastic order quantifies the concept of one random variable being "bigger" than another. These are usually partial orders, so that one random variable

A

may be neither stochastically greater than, less than, nor equal to another random variable

B

. Many different orders exist, which have different applications.

Usual stochastic order

A real random variable

A

is less than a random variable

B

in the "usual stochastic order" if

\Pr(A>x)\le\Pr(B>x)forallx\in(-infty,infty),

where

\Pr()

denotes the probability of an event. This is sometimes denoted

A\preceqB

or

A\lestB

.

If additionally

\Pr(A>x)<\Pr(B>x)

for some

x

, then

A

is stochastically strictly less than

B

, sometimes denoted

A\precB

. In decision theory, under this circumstance, is said to be first-order stochastically dominant over A.

Characterizations

The following rules describe situations when one random variable is stochastically less than or equal to another. Strict version of some of these rules also exist.

A\preceqB

if and only if for all non-decreasing functions

u

,

{\rmE}[u(A)]\le{\rmE}[u(B)]

.
  1. If

u

is non-decreasing and

A\preceqB

then

u(A)\precequ(B)

  1. If

u:Rn\toR

is increasing in each variable and

Ai

and

Bi

are independent sets of random variables with

Ai\preceqBi

for each

i

, then

u(A1,...,An)\precequ(B1,...,Bn)

and in particular
n
\sum
i=1

Ai\preceq

n
\sum
i=1

Bi

Moreover, the

i

th order statistics satisfy

A(i)\preceqB(i)

.
  1. If two sequences of random variables

Ai

and

Bi

, with

Ai\preceqBi

for all

i

each converge in distribution, then their limits satisfy

A\preceqB

.
  1. If

A

,

B

and

C

are random variables such that

\sumc\Pr(C=c)=1

and

\Pr(A>u|C=c)\le\Pr(B>u|C=c)

for all

u

and

c

such that

\Pr(C=c)>0

, then

A\preceqB

.

Other properties

If

A\preceqB

and

{\rmE}[A]={\rmE}[B]

then

Al{\overset{d}{=}}B

(the random variables are equal in distribution).

Stochastic dominance

Stochastic dominance relations are a family of stochastic orderings used in decision theory:[1]

A\prec(0)B

if and only if

A\leB

for all realizations of these random variables and

A<B

for at least one realization.

A\prec(1)B

if and only if

\Pr(A>x)\le\Pr(B>x)

for all

x

and there exists

x

such that

\Pr(A>x)<\Pr(B>x)

.

A\prec(2)B

if and only if
x
\int
-infty

[\Pr(B>t)-\Pr(A>t)]dt\geq0

for all

x

, with strict inequality at some

x

.

There also exist higher-order notions of stochastic dominance. With the definitions above, we have

A\prec(i)B\impliesA\prec(i+1)B

.

Multivariate stochastic order

An

Rd

-valued random variable

A

is less than an

Rd

-valued random variable

B

in the "usual stochastic order" if

{\rmE}[f(A)]\le{\rmE}[f(B)]forallbounded,increasingfunctionsf\colonRd\longrightarrowR

Other types of multivariate stochastic orders exist. For instance the upper and lower orthant order which are similar to the usual one-dimensional stochastic order.

A

is said to be smaller than

B

in upper orthant order if

\Pr(A>x)\le\Pr(B>x)forallx\inRd

and

A

is smaller than

B

in lower orthant order if[2]

\Pr(A\lex)\le\Pr(B\lex)forallx\inRd

All three order types also have integral representations, that is for a particular order

A

is smaller than

B

if and only if

{\rmE}[f(A)]\le{\rmE}[f(B)]

for all

f\colonRd\longrightarrowR

in a class of functions

lG

.[3]

lG

is then called generator of the respective order.

Other dominance orders

The following stochastic orders are useful in the theory of random social choice. They are used to compare the outcomes of random social choice functions, in order to check them for efficiency or other desirable criteria.[4] The dominance orders below are ordered from the most conservative to the least conservative. They are exemplified on random variables over the finite support .

Deterministic dominance, denoted

A\succeqddB

, means that every possible outcome of

A

is at least as good as every possible outcome of

B

: for all x<y,

\Pr[A=x]\Pr[B=y]=0

. In other words:

\Pr[A\geqB]=1

. For example,

0.6*30+0.4*20\succeqdd0.5*20+0.5*10

.

Bilinear dominance, denoted

A\succeqbdB

, means that, for every possible outcome, the probability that

A

yields the better one and

B

yields the worse one is at least as large as the probability the other way around: for all x

\Pr[A=x]\Pr[B=y]\leq\Pr[A=y]\Pr[B=x]

For example,

0.5*30+0.5*20\succeqbd0.33*30+0.33*20+0.34*10

.

Stochastic dominance (already mentioned above), denoted

A\succeqsdB

, means that, for every possible outcome x, the probability that

A

yields at least x is at least as large as the probability that

B

yields at least x: for all x,

\Pr[A\geqx]\geq\Pr[B\geqx]

. For example,

0.5*30+0.5*10\succeqsd0.5*20+0.5*10

.

Pairwise-comparison dominance, denoted

A\succeqpcB

, means that the probability that that

A

yields a better outcome than

B

is larger than the other way around:

\Pr[A\geqB]\geq\Pr[B\geqA]

. For example,

0.67*30+0.33*10\succeqpc1.0*20

.

Downward-lexicographic dominance, denoted

A\succeqdlB

, means that

A

has a larger probability than

B

of returning the best outcome, or both

A

and

B

have the same probability to return the best outcome but

A

has a larger probability than

B

of returning the second-best best outcome, etc. Upward-lexicographic dominance is defined analogously based on the probability to return the worst outcomes. See lexicographic dominance.

Other stochastic orders

Hazard rate order

The hazard rate of a non-negative random variable

X

with absolutely continuous distribution function

F

and density function

f

is defined as

r(t)=

d
dt

(-log(1-F(t)))=

f(t)
1-F(t)

.

Given two non-negative variables

X

and

Y

with absolutely continuous distribution

F

and

G

, and with hazard rate functions

r

and

q

, respectively,

X

is said to be smaller than

Y

in the hazard rate order (denoted as

X\preceqhrY

) if

r(t)\geq(t)

for all

t\ge0

,or equivalently if
1-F(t)
1-G(t)
is decreasing in

t

.

Likelihood ratio order

Let

X

and

Y

two continuous (or discrete) random variables with densities (or discrete densities)

f\left(t\right)

and

g\left(t\right)

, respectively, so that
g\left(t\right)
f\left(t\right)
increases in

t

over the union of the supports of

X

and

Y

; in this case,

X

is smaller than

Y

in the likelihood ratio order (

X\preceqlrY

).

Variability orders

If two variables have the same mean, they can still be compared by how "spread out" their distributions are. This is captured to a limited extent by the variance, but more fully by a range of stochastic orders.

Convex order

Convex order is a special kind of variability order. Under the convex ordering,

A

is less than

B

if and only if for all convex

u

,

{\rmE}[u(A)]\leq{\rmE}[u(B)]

.

Laplace transform order

Laplace transform order compares both size and variability of two random variables. Similar to convex order, Laplace transform order is established by comparing the expectation of a function of the random variable where the function is from a special class:

u(x)=-\exp(-\alphax)

. This makes the Laplace transform order an integral stochastic order with the generator set given by the function set defined above with

\alpha

a positive real number.

Realizable monotonicity

Considering a family of probability distributions

({P}\alpha)\alpha

on partially ordered space

(E,\preceq)

indexed with

\alpha\inF

(where

(F,\preceq)

is another partially ordered space, the concept of complete or realizable monotonicity may be defined. It means, there exists a family of random variables

(X\alpha)\alpha

on the same probability space, such that the distribution of

X\alpha

is

{P}\alpha

and

X\alpha\preceqX\beta

almost surely whenever

\alpha\preceq\beta

. It means the existence of a monotone coupling. See[5]

See also

Bibliography

Notes and References

  1. Book: Perrakis . Stylianos . Stochastic Dominance Option Pricing . Palgrave Macmillan, Cham . 2019 . 978-3-030-11589-0 . 10.1007/978-3-030-11590-6_1 .
  2. Definition 2.3 in Thibaut Lux, Antonin Papapantoleon: "Improved Fréchet-Hoeffding bounds for d-copulas and applications in model-free finance." Annals of Applied Probability 27, 3633-3671, 2017
  3. Alfred Müller, Dietrich Stoyan: Comparison methods for stochastic models and risks. Wiley, Chichester 2002,, S. 2.
  4. Book: Felix Brandt. https://books.google.com/books?id=0qY8DwAAQBAJ&dq=multiwinner++voting+a+new+challenge&pg=PA27. Trends in Computational Social Choice. 2017-10-26. Lulu.com. 978-1-326-91209-3. Endriss. Ulle. en. Roling the Dice: Recent Results in Probabilistic Social Choice.
  5. Stochastic Monotonicity and Realizable MonotonicityJames Allen Fill and Motoya Machida, The Annals of Probability, Vol. 29, No. 2 (Apr., 2001), pp. 938-978, Published by: Institute of Mathematical Statistics, Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2691998