Set-theoretic limit explained

A1,A2,\ldots

(subsets of a common set

X

) is a set whose elements are determined by the sequence in either of two equivalent ways: (1) by upper and lower bounds on the sequence that converge monotonically to the same set (analogous to convergence of real-valued sequences) and (2) by convergence of a sequence of indicator functions which are themselves real-valued. As is the case with sequences of other objects, convergence is not necessary or even usual.

More generally, again analogous to real-valued sequences, the less restrictive limit infimum and limit supremum of a set sequence always exist and can be used to determine convergence: the limit exists if the limit infimum and limit supremum are identical. (See below). Such set limits are essential in measure theory and probability.

It is a common misconception that the limits infimum and supremum described here involve sets of accumulation points, that is, sets of

x=\limkxk,

where each

xk

is in some
A
nk

.

This is only true if convergence is determined by the discrete metric (that is,

xn\tox

if there is

N

such that

xn=x

for all

n\geqN

). This article is restricted to that situation as it is the only one relevant for measure theory and probability. See the examples below. (On the other hand, there are more general topological notions of set convergence that do involve accumulation points under different metrics or topologies.)

Definitions

The two definitions

Suppose that

\left(An\right)

infty
n=1
is a sequence of sets. The two equivalent definitions are as follows.

An

exists and is equal to that common set. Either set as described above can be used to get the limit, and there may be other means to get the limit as well.
1
An

(x)

equal

1

if

x\inAn,

and

0

otherwise. Define[1] \liminf_ A_n = \Bigl\ and \limsup_ A_n = \Bigl\, where the expressions inside the brackets on the right are, respectively, the limit infimum and limit supremum of the real-valued sequence
1
An

(x).

Again, if these two sets are equal, then the set-theoretic limit of the sequence

An

exists and is equal to that common set, and either set as described above can be used to get the limit.

To see the equivalence of the definitions, consider the limit infimum. The use of De Morgan's law below explains why this suffices for the limit supremum. Since indicator functions take only values

0

and

1,

\liminfn

1
An

(x)=1

if and only if
1
An

(x)

takes value

0

only finitely many times. Equivalently, x \in \bigcup_ \bigcap_ A_j if and only if there exists

n

such that the element is in

Am

for every

m\geqn,

which is to say if and only if

x\not\inAn

for only finitely many

n.

Therefore,

x

is in the

\liminfnAn

if and only if

x

is in all but finitely many

An.

For this reason, a shorthand phrase for the limit infimum is "

x

is in

An

all but finitely often", typically expressed by writing "

An

a.b.f.o.".

Similarly, an element

x

is in the limit supremum if, no matter how large

n

is, there exists

m\geqn

such that the element is in

Am.

That is,

x

is in the limit supremum if and only if

x

is in infinitely many

An.

For this reason, a shorthand phrase for the limit supremum is "

x

is in

An

infinitely often", typically expressed by writing "

An

i.o.".

To put it another way, the limit infimum consists of elements that "eventually stay forever" (are in set after

n

), while the limit supremum consists of elements that "never leave forever" (are in set after

n

). Or more formally:
\lim_A_n = L \quad \Longleftrightarrow     for every

x\inL

      there is a

n0\in\N

with

x\inAn

for all

n\gen0

and
for every

y\inX\setminus\

L there is a

p0\in\N

with

y\not\inAp

for all

p\gep0

.

Monotone sequences

The sequence

\left(An\right)

is said to be nonincreasing if

An+1\subseteqAn

for each

n,

and nondecreasing if

An\subseteqAn+1

for each

n.

In each of these cases the set limit exists. Consider, for example, a nonincreasing sequence

\left(An\right).

Then \bigcap_ A_j = \bigcap_ A_j \text \bigcup_ A_j = A_n.From these it follows that\liminf_ A_n = \bigcup_ \bigcap_ A_j = \bigcap_ A_j = \bigcap_ \bigcup_ A_j = \limsup_ A_n.Similarly, if

\left(An\right)

is nondecreasing then \lim_ A_n = \bigcup_ A_j.

The Cantor set is defined this way.

Properties

1
An

(x),

as

n

goes to infinity, exists for all

x

then \lim_ A_n = \left\. Otherwise, the limit for

\left(An\right)

does not exist.

x\inAn

all but finitely often implies

x\inAn

infinitely often.

Ac:=X\setminusA,

\liminf_ A_n = \bigcup_n \left(\bigcup_ A_j^c\right)^c= \left(\bigcap_n \bigcup_ A_j^c\right)^c= \left(\limsup_ A_n^c\right)^c. That is,

x\inAn

all but finitely often is the same as

x\not\inAn

finitely often.

l{F}

is a -algebra of subsets of

X.

That is,

l{F}

is nonempty and is closed under complement and under unions and intersections of countably many sets. Then, by the first definition above, if each

An\inl{F}

then both

\liminfnAn

and

\limsupnAn

are elements of

l{F}.

Examples

An=\left(-\tfrac{1}{n},1-\tfrac{1}{n}\right].

Then\liminf_ A_n = \bigcup_n \bigcap_ \left(-\tfrac, 1 - \tfrac \right] = \bigcup_n \left[0, 1 - \tfrac{1}{n}\right] = [0, 1)</math> and <math display=block>\limsup_{n \to \infty} A_n = \bigcap_n \bigcup_{j \geq n}\left(-\tfrac{1}{j}, 1 - \tfrac{1}{j}\right] = \bigcap_n \left(- \tfrac, 1\right) = [0, 1)</math> so <math>\lim_{n \to \infty} A_n = [0, 1)</math> exists. * Change the previous example to <math>A_n = \left(\tfrac{(-1)^n}{n}, 1 - \tfrac{(-1)^n}{n}\right]. Then\liminf_ A_n = \bigcup_n \bigcap_ \left(\tfrac, 1-\tfrac\right] = \bigcup_n \left(\tfrac, 1 - \tfrac\right] = (0, 1)and\limsup_ A_n = \bigcap_n \bigcup_ \left(\tfrac, 1 - \tfrac\right] = \bigcap_n \left(-\tfrac, 1 + \tfrac\right] = [0, 1],so

\limnAn

does not exist, despite the fact that the left and right endpoints of the intervals converge to 0 and 1, respectively.

An=\left\{0,\tfrac{1}{n},\tfrac{2}{n},\ldots,\tfrac{n-1}{n},1\right\}.

Then\bigcup_ A_j = \Q\cap[0,1]is the set of all rational numbers between 0 and 1 (inclusive), since even for

j<n

and

0\leqk\leqj,

\tfrac{k}{j}=\tfrac{nk}{nj}

is an element of the above. Therefore,\limsup_ A_n = \Q \cap [0, 1].On the other hand, \bigcap_ A_j = \, which implies\liminf_ A_n = \.In this case, the sequence

A1,A2,\ldots

does not have a limit. Note that

\limnAn

is not the set of accumulation points, which would be the entire interval

[0,1]

(according to the usual Euclidean metric).

Probability uses

Set limits, particularly the limit infimum and the limit supremum, are essential for probability and measure theory. Such limits are used to calculate (or prove) the probabilities and measures of other, more purposeful, sets. For the following,

(X,l{F},P)

is a probability space, which means

l{F}

is a σ-algebra of subsets of

X

and

P

is a probability measure defined on that σ-algebra. Sets in the σ-algebra are known as events.

If

A1,A2,\ldots

is a monotone sequence of events in

l{F}

then

\limnAn

exists and\mathbb\left(\lim_ A_n\right) = \lim_ \mathbb\left(A_n\right).

Borel–Cantelli lemmas

See main article: article and Borel–Cantelli lemma. In probability, the two Borel–Cantelli lemmas can be useful for showing that the limsup of a sequence of events has probability equal to 1 or to 0. The statement of the first (original) Borel–Cantelli lemma isThe second Borel–Cantelli lemma is a partial converse:

Almost sure convergence

One of the most important applications to probability is for demonstrating the almost sure convergence of a sequence of random variables. The event that a sequence of random variables

Y1,Y2,\ldots

converges to another random variable

Y

is formally expressed as \left\. It would be a mistake, however, to write this simply as a limsup of events. That is, this the event \limsup_ \left\! Instead, the of the event is \begin\left\&= \left\\\ &= \bigcup_ \bigcap_ \bigcup_ \left\ \\&= \lim_ \limsup_ \left\.\endTherefore,\mathbb\left(\left\\right) = \lim_ \mathbb\left(\limsup_ \left\\right).

Notes and References

  1. Book: Resnick. Sidney I.. A Probability Path. 1998. Birkhäuser. Boston. 3-7643-4055-X.
  2. Book: Gut, Allan . Probability: A Graduate Course: A Graduate Course . 2013 . Springer New York . 978-1-4614-4707-8 . Springer Texts in Statistics . 75 . New York, NY . en . 10.1007/978-1-4614-4708-5.