Rubinstein bargaining model explained

A Rubinstein bargaining model refers to a class of bargaining games that feature alternating offers through an infinite time horizon. The original proof is due to Ariel Rubinstein in a 1982 paper.[1] For a long time, the solution to this type of game was a mystery; thus, Rubinstein's solution is one of the most influential findings in game theory.

Requirements

A standard Rubinstein bargaining model has the following elements:

Solution

Consider the typical Rubinstein bargaining game in which two players decide how to divide a pie of size 1. An offer by a player takes the form x = (x1, x2) with x1 + x2 = 1 and

x1,x2\geqslant0

. Assume the players discount at the geometric rate of d, which can be interpreted as cost of delay or "pie spoiling". That is, 1 step later, the pie is worth d times what it was, for some d with 0<d<1.

Any x can be a Nash equilibrium outcome of this game, resulting from the following strategy profile: Player 1 always proposes x = (x1, x2) and only accepts offers x where x1' ≥ x1. Player 2 always proposes x = (x1, x2) and only accepts offers x where x2' ≥ x2.

In the above Nash equilibrium, player 2's threat to reject any offer less than x2 is not credible. In the subgame where player 1 did offer x2' where x2 > x2' > d x2, clearly player 2's best response is to accept.

To derive a sufficient condition for subgame perfect equilibrium, let x = (x1, x2) and y = (y1, y2) be two divisions of the pie with the following property:

  1. x2 = d y2, and
  2. y1 = d x1,

i.e.

  1. x = (x1, x2), and
  2. y = (d x1,
1
d

x2

).

Consider the strategy profile where player 1 offers x and accepts no less than y1, and player 2 offers y and accepts no less than x2. Player 2 is now indifferent between accepting and rejecting, therefore the threat to reject lesser offers is now credible. Same applies to a subgame in which it is player 1's turn to decide whether to accept or reject. In this subgame perfect equilibrium, player 1 gets 1/(1+d) while player 2 gets d/(1+d). This subgame perfect equilibrium is essentially unique.

A Generalization

When the discount factor is different for the two players,

d1

for the first one and

d2

for the second, let us denote the value for the first player as

v(d1,d2)

.Then a reasoning similar to the above gives

1-v(d1,d2)=d2 x v(d2,d1)


1-v(d2,d1)=d1 x v(d1,d2)

yielding

v(d1,d2)=

1-d2
1-d1d2
. This expression reduces to the original one for

d1=d2=d

.

Desirability

Rubinstein bargaining has become pervasive in the literature because it has many desirable qualities:

Further reading

. Roger Myerson . Game Theory: Analysis of Conflict . Cambridge . Harvard University Press . 1991 . 978-0-674-34115-9 . 394–408 .

Notes and References

  1. Rubinstein, Ariel . 1982 . Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model . Econometrica . 50 . 1 . 97–109 . 10.2307/1912531 . 1912531 . 10.1.1.295.1434 . 14827857 .