In mathematics, the Radon–Nikodym theorem is a result in measure theory that expresses the relationship between two measures defined on the same measurable space. A measure is a set function that assigns a consistent magnitude to the measurable subsets of a measurable space. Examples of a measure include area and volume, where the subsets are sets of points; or the probability of an event, which is a subset of possible outcomes within a wider probability space.
One way to derive a new measure from one already given is to assign a density to each point of the space, then integrate over the measurable subset of interest. This can be expressed as
\nu(A)=\intAfd\mu,
where is the new measure being defined for any measurable subset and the function is the density at a given point. The integral is with respect to an existing measure, which may often be the canonical Lebesgue measure on the real line or the n-dimensional Euclidean space (corresponding to our standard notions of length, area and volume). For example, if represented mass density and was the Lebesgue measure in three-dimensional space, then would equal the total mass in a spatial region .
The Radon–Nikodym theorem essentially states that, under certain conditions, any measure can be expressed in this way with respect to another measure on the same space. The function is then called the Radon–Nikodym derivative and is denoted by
\tfrac{d\nu}{d\mu}
The theorem is named after Johann Radon, who proved the theorem for the special case where the underlying space is in 1913, and for Otto Nikodym who proved the general case in 1930.[2] In 1936 Hans Freudenthal generalized the Radon–Nikodym theorem by proving the Freudenthal spectral theorem, a result in Riesz space theory; this contains the Radon–Nikodym theorem as a special case.[3]
A Banach space is said to have the Radon–Nikodym property if the generalization of the Radon–Nikodym theorem also holds, mutatis mutandis, for functions with values in . All Hilbert spaces have the Radon–Nikodym property.
(X,\Sigma)
\mu
\nu.
\nu\ll\mu
\nu
\mu
\Sigma
f:X\to[0,infty),
A\in\Sigma,
The function
f
g
f=g
f
A similar theorem can be proven for signed and complex measures: namely, that if
\mu
\nu
\nu\ll\mu,
\nu
\mu,
\mu
g
X
A,
In the following examples, the set is the real interval [0,1], and
\Sigma
\mu
\nu
\mu
\nu
\nu
\mu
(0.1-\varepsilon)
(0.1+\varepsilon)
1
\varepsilon>0
\mu=\nu+\delta0
\nu
\delta0
\nu
\mu
x=0
x>0
The theorem is very important in extending the ideas of probability theory from probability masses and probability densities defined over real numbers to probability measures defined over arbitrary sets. It tells if and how it is possible to change from one probability measure to another. Specifically, the probability density function of a random variable is the Radon–Nikodym derivative of the induced measure with respect to some base measure (usually the Lebesgue measure for continuous random variables).
For example, it can be used to prove the existence of conditional expectation for probability measures. The latter itself is a key concept in probability theory, as conditional probability is just a special case of it.
Amongst other fields, financial mathematics uses the theorem extensively, in particular via the Girsanov theorem. Such changes of probability measure are the cornerstone of the rational pricing of derivatives and are used for converting actual probabilities into those of the risk neutral probabilities.
If μ and ν are measures over, and μ ≪ ν
The Radon–Nikodym theorem above makes the assumption that the measure μ with respect to which one computes the rate of change of ν is σ-finite.
Here is an example when μ is not σ-finite and the Radon–Nikodym theorem fails to hold.
Consider the Borel σ-algebra on the real line. Let the counting measure,, of a Borel set be defined as the number of elements of if is finite, and otherwise. One can check that is indeed a measure. It is not -finite, as not every Borel set is at most a countable union of finite sets. Let be the usual Lebesgue measure on this Borel algebra. Then, is absolutely continuous with respect to, since for a set one has only if is the empty set, and then is also zero.
Assume that the Radon–Nikodym theorem holds, that is, for some measurable function one has
\nu(A)=\intAfd\mu
for all Borel sets. Taking to be a singleton set,, and using the above equality, one finds
0=f(a)
for all real numbers . This implies that the function, and therefore the Lebesgue measure, is zero, which is a contradiction.
Assuming
\nu\ll\mu,
\mu
\nu
\mu
\nu(A)=\sup\{\nu(B):B\in{\cal
\operatorname{pre}(\R | |
P}(A)\cap\mu | |
\ge0 |
)\}
A\in\Sigma.
This section gives a measure-theoretic proof of the theorem. There is also a functional-analytic proof, using Hilbert space methods, that was first given by von Neumann.
For finite measures and, the idea is to consider functions with . The supremum of all such functions, along with the monotone convergence theorem, then furnishes the Radon–Nikodym derivative. The fact that the remaining part of is singular with respect to follows from a technical fact about finite measures. Once the result is established for finite measures, extending to -finite, signed, and complex measures can be done naturally. The details are given below.
Constructing an extended-valued candidate First, suppose and are both finite-valued nonnegative measures. Let be the set of those extended-value measurable functions such that:
\forallA\in\Sigma: \intAfd\mu\leq\nu(A)
, since it contains at least the zero function. Now let, and suppose is an arbitrary measurable set, and define:
\begin{align} A1&=\left\{x\inA:f1(x)>f2(x)\right\},\\ A2&=\left\{x\inA:f2(x)\geqf1(x)\right\}. \end{align}
Then one has
\intAmax\left\{f1,f2\right\}d\mu=
\int | |
A1 |
f1d\mu+
\int | |
A2 |
f2d\mu\leq\nu\left(A1\right)+\nu\left(A2\right)=\nu(A),
and therefore, .
Now, let be a sequence of functions in such that
\limn\toinfty\intXfnd\mu=\supf\in\intXfd\mu.
By replacing with the maximum of the first functions, one can assume that the sequence is increasing. Let be an extended-valued function defined as
g(x):=\limn\toinftyfn(x).
By Lebesgue's monotone convergence theorem, one has
\limn\toinfty\intAfnd\mu=\intA\limn\toinftyfn(x)d\mu(x)=\intAgd\mu\leq\nu(A)
for each, and hence, . Also, by the construction of,
\intXgd\mu=\supf\in\intXfd\mu.
Proving equality Now, since,
\nu0(A):=\nu(A)-\intAgd\mu
defines a nonnegative measure on . To prove equality, we show that .
Suppose ; then, since is finite, there is an such that . To derive a contradiction from, we look for a positive set for the signed measure (i.e. a measurable set, all of whose measurable subsets have non-negative measure), where also has positive -measure. Conceptually, we're looking for a set, where in every part of . A convenient approach is to use the Hahn decomposition for the signed measure .
Note then that for every one has, and hence,
\begin{align} \nu(A)&=\intAgd\mu+\nu0(A)\\ &\geq\intAgd\mu+\nu0(A\capP)\\ &\geq\intAgd\mu+\varepsilon\mu(A\capP) =\intA\left(g+\varepsilon1P\right)d\mu, \end{align}
where is the indicator function of . Also, note that as desired; for if, then (since is absolutely continuous in relation to), so and
\nu0(X)-\varepsilon\mu(X)=\left(\nu0-\varepsilon\mu\right)(N)\leq0,
Then, since also
\intX\left(g+\varepsilon1P\right)d\mu\leq\nu(X)<+infty,
and satisfies
\intX\left(g+\varepsilon1P\right)d\mu>\intXgd\mu=\supf\in\intXfd\mu.
This is impossible because it violates the definition of a supremum; therefore, the initial assumption that must be false. Hence,, as desired.
Restricting to finite values Now, since is -integrable, the set is -null. Therefore, if a is defined as
f(x)=\begin{cases} g(x)&ifg(x)<infty\\ 0&otherwise, \end{cases}
then has the desired properties.
Uniqueness As for the uniqueness, let be measurable functions satisfying
\nu(A)=\intAfd\mu=\intAgd\mu
for every measurable set . Then, is -integrable, and
\intA(g-f)d\mu=0.
In particular, for or . It follows that
\intX(g-f)+d\mu=0=\intX(g-f)-d\mu,
and so, that -almost everywhere; the same is true for, and thus, -almost everywhere, as desired.
If and are -finite, then can be written as the union of a sequence of disjoint sets in, each of which has finite measure under both and . For each, by the finite case, there is a -measurable function such that
\nun(A)=\intAfnd\mu
for each -measurable subset of . The sum of those functions is then the required function such that .
As for the uniqueness, since each of the is -almost everywhere unique, so is .
If is a -finite signed measure, then it can be Hahn–Jordan decomposed as where one of the measures is finite. Applying the previous result to those two measures, one obtains two functions,, satisfying the Radon–Nikodym theorem for and respectively, at least one of which is -integrable (i.e., its integral with respect to is finite). It is clear then that satisfies the required properties, including uniqueness, since both and are unique up to -almost everywhere equality.
If is a complex measure, it can be decomposed as, where both and are finite-valued signed measures. Applying the above argument, one obtains two functions,, satisfying the required properties for and, respectively. Clearly, is the required function.
Lebesgue's decomposition theorem shows that the assumptions of the Radon–Nikodym theorem can be found even in a situation which is seemingly more general. Consider a σ-finite positive measure
\mu
(X,\Sigma)
\nu
\Sigma
\nua
\nus
\Sigma
\nu=\nua+\nus
\nua\ll\mu
\nus\perp\mu
\nua,\mu