Pi-system explained
is a
collection
of certain
subsets of
such that
is
non-empty.
then
That is,
is a non-empty family of subsets of
that is
closed under non-empty finite
intersections.
[1] The importance of -systems arises from the fact that if two
probability measures agree on a -system, then they agree on the
-algebra generated by that -system. Moreover, if other properties, such as equality of integrals, hold for the -system, then they hold for the generated -algebra as well. This is the case whenever the collection of subsets for which the property holds is a
-system. -systems are also useful for checking independence of random variables.
This is desirable because in practice, -systems are often simpler to work with than -algebras. For example, it may be awkward to work with -algebras generated by infinitely many sets
So instead we may examine the union of all -algebras generated by finitely many sets
This forms a -system that generates the desired -algebra. Another example is the collection of all
intervals of the
real line, along with the empty set, which is a -system that generates the very important
Borel -algebra of subsets of the real line.
Definitions
A -system is a non-empty collection of sets
that is closed under non-empty finite intersections, which is equivalent to
containing the intersection of any two of its elements. If every set in this -system is a subset of
then it is called a
of subsets of
there exists a -system
called the
, that is the unique smallest -system of
containing every element of
It is equal to the intersection of all -systems containing
and can be explicitly described as the set of all possible non-empty finite intersections of elements of
A non-empty family of sets has the finite intersection property if and only if the -system it generates does not contain the empty set as an element.
Examples
and
the intervals
form a -system, and the intervals
form a -system if the empty set is also included.
- The topology (collection of open subsets) of any topological space is a -system.
- Every filter is a -system. Every -system that doesn't contain the empty set is a prefilter (also known as a filter base).
the set
l{I}f=\left\{f-1((-infty,x]):x\in\Reals\right\}
defines a -system, and is called the -system by
(Alternatively,
\left\{f-1((a,b]):a,b\in\Reals,a<b\right\}\cup\{\varnothing\}
defines a -system generated by
)
and
are -systems for
and
respectively, then
\{A1 x A2:A1\inP1,A2\inP2\}
is a -system for the
Cartesian product
- Every -algebra is a -system.
Relationship to -systems
A -system on
is a set
of subsets of
satisfying
then
is a sequence of
(pairwise) subsets in
then
Whilst it is true that any -algebra satisfies the properties of being both a -system and a -system, it is not true that any -system is a -system, and moreover it is not true that any -system is a -algebra. However, a useful classification is that any set system which is both a -system and a -system is a -algebra. This is used as a step in proving the - theorem.
The - theorem
Let
be a -system, and let
be a -system contained in
The - theorem
[2] states that the -algebra
generated by
is contained in
The - theorem can be used to prove many elementary measure theoretic results. For instance, it is used in proving the uniqueness claim of the Carathéodory extension theorem for -finite measures.[3]
The - theorem is closely related to the monotone class theorem, which provides a similar relationship between monotone classes and algebras, and can be used to derive many of the same results. Since -systems are simpler classes than algebras, it can be easier to identify the sets that are in them while, on the other hand, checking whether the property under consideration determines a -system is often relatively easy. Despite the difference between the two theorems, the - theorem is sometimes referred to as the monotone class theorem.[2]
Example
Let
be two measures on the -algebra
and suppose that
is generated by a -system
If
for all
and
\mu1(\Omega)=\mu2(\Omega)<infty,
then
This is the uniqueness statement of the Carathéodory extension theorem for finite measures. If this result does not seem very remarkable, consider the fact that it usually is very difficult or even impossible to fully describe every set in the -algebra, and so the problem of equating measures would be completely hopeless without such a tool.
Idea of the proof[3] Define the collection of setsBy the first assumption,
and
agree on
and thus
By the second assumption,
and it can further be shown that
is a -system. It follows from the - theorem that
\sigma(I)\subseteqD\subseteq\sigma(I),
and so
That is to say, the measures agree on
-Systems in probability
-systems are more commonly used in the study of probability theory than in the general field of measure theory. This is primarily due to probabilistic notions such as independence, though it may also be a consequence of the fact that the - theorem was proven by the probabilist Eugene Dynkin. Standard measure theory texts typically prove the same results via monotone classes, rather than -systems.
Equality in distribution
X:(\Omega,lF,\operatornameP)\to\Reals
in terms of its
cumulative distribution function. Recall that the cumulative distribution of a random variable is defined as
whereas the seemingly more general of the variable is the probability measure
where
is the Borel -algebra. The random variables
X:(\Omega,lF,\operatornameP)\to\Reals
and
Y:(\tilde\Omega,\tilde{lF},\tilde{\operatornameP})\to\Reals
(on two possibly different
probability spaces) are (or), denoted by
if they have the same cumulative distribution functions; that is, if
The motivation for the definition stems from the observation that if
then that is exactly to say that
and
agree on the -system
\{(-infty,a]:a\in\Reals\}
which generates
and so by the example above:
A similar result holds for the joint distribution of a random vector. For example, suppose
and
are two random variables defined on the same probability space
(\Omega,l{F},\operatorname{P}),
with respectively generated -systems
and
The joint cumulative distribution function of
is
However,
A=X-1((-infty,a])\inl{I}X
and
B=Y-1((-infty,b])\inl{I}Y.
Because
is a -system generated by the random pair
the - theorem is used to show that the joint cumulative distribution function suffices to determine the joint law of
In other words,
and
have the same distribution if and only if they have the same joint cumulative distribution function.
In the theory of stochastic processes, two processes
are known to be equal in distribution if and only if they agree on all finite-dimensional distributions; that is, for all
The proof of this is another application of the - theorem.[4]
Independent random variables
The theory of -system plays an important role in the probabilistic notion of independence. If
and
are two random variables defined on the same probability space
(\Omega,l{F},\operatorname{P})
then the random variables are independent if and only if their -systems
satisfy for all
and
which is to say that
are independent. This actually is a special case of the use of -systems for determining the distribution of
Example
Let
where
are
iid standard normal random variables. Define the radius and argument (arctan) variables
Then
and
are independent random variables.
To prove this, it is sufficient to show that the -systems
are independent: that is, for all
and
Confirming that this is the case is an exercise in changing variables. Fix
and
then the probability can be expressed as an integral of the probability density function of
References
- Book: Gut, Allan. Allan Gut. Probability: A Graduate Course. 2005. Springer Texts in Statistics. Springer. New York. 10.1007/b138932. 0-387-22833-0.
- Book: Williams, David. David Williams (mathematician). Probability with Martingales. 1991. Cambridge University Press. 0-521-40605-6.
Notes and References
- The nullary (0-ary) intersection of subsets of
is by convention equal to
which is not required to be an element of a -system.
- Kallenberg, Foundations Of Modern Probability, p. 2
- Durrett, Probability Theory and Examples, p. 404
- Kallenberg, Foundations Of Modern Probability, p. 48