Paternalism Explained

Paternalism is action that limits a person's or group's liberty or autonomy and is intended to promote their own good. Paternalism can also imply that the behavior is against or regardless of the will of a person, or also that the behavior expresses an attitude of superiority.[1] Paternalism, paternalistic and paternalist have all been used as a pejorative for example in the context of societal and/or political realms and references.

Some such as John Stuart Mill think paternalism can be appropriate towards children, saying:

Paternalism towards adults is sometimes thought of as treating them as if they were children.[2]

Etymology

The word paternalism derives from the adjective paternal, which entered the English language in the fifteenth century from Old French paternel (cf. Old Occitan paternal, as in Catalan, Spanish and Portuguese), itself from Medieval Latin paternalis.[3] The classical Latin equivalent was paternus "fatherly", from pater "father".[4]

Types

Soft and hard

Soft paternalism is the view that paternalism is justified only if an action to be committed is involuntary. John Stuart Mill gives the example of a person about to walk across a damaged bridge. One cannot tell the person the bridge is damaged as he does not speak our language. According to soft paternalism, one would be justified in forcing him to not cross the bridge so one could find out whether he knows about the damage. If he knows and wants to jump off the bridge and commit suicide then one should allow him to. Hard paternalists say that at least sometimes one is entitled to prevent him from crossing the bridge and committing suicide.[5]

Pure and impure

Pure paternalism is paternalism where the people having their liberty or autonomy taken away are those being protected. Impure paternalism occurs when the class of people whose liberty or autonomy is violated by some measure is wider than the group of persons thereby protected.[5]

Moral and welfare

Moral paternalism is where paternalism is justified to promote the moral well-being of a person(s) even if their welfare would not improve. For example, it could be argued that someone should be prevented from prostitution even if they make a decent living off it and their health is protected. A moral paternalist would argue that it is ethical considering they believe prostitution to be morally corrupting.[5]

Criteria for effective paternalism

Thomas Pogge argues that there are a number of criteria for paternalism.[6]

Opponents

See also: Social engineering (political science) and Nanny state. In his Two Treatises of Government, John Locke argues (against Robert Filmer) that political and paternal power are not the same.

John Stuart Mill opposes state paternalism on the grounds that individuals know their own good better than the state does, that the moral equality of persons demands respect for others' liberty, and that paternalism disrupts the development of an independent character. In On Liberty, he writes:

Mill, however, disregards his own analysis when it comes to colonial subjects. In On Liberty, he writes:

Mill above declares barbarians to be in need of paternalism. But he narrowly defines barbarism historically, geographically, and economically insofar as to declare it fit to describe the people he intends to describe as such.

Contemporary opponents of paternalism often appeal to the ideal of personal autonomy.

In society

Paternalism and slavery

Walter Johnson introduces a concept of paternalism in that mentions "Slave-market paternalism thus replayed the plots of proslavery propaganda and fiction: the good hearted slave at the side of the dying master; the slave who could be trusted to master himself; the slaveholder's saving interventions in the life of the unfortunate slave".[9] Even though slaves could benefit from the concept of paternalism by receiving abundant food and medical care, the concept can never justify the institution of slavery. Some libertarians consider paternalism, especially when imposed by the state to be a form of modern slavery.

See also

Further reading

Notes and References

  1. Shiffrin, Seana. 2000. "Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation". Philosophy and Public Affairs 29(3): 205–250.
  2. Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Harm to Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 4
  3. Web site: Paternal - Adjective . Oxford English Dictionary Online . March 2021 . . 28 April 2021.
  4. Web site: Paternal (adjective) . . 21 December 2023.
  5. Book: Paternalism . Dworkin, Gerald. Edward N. Zalta . 2020 . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  6. Book: Pogge. Thomas. World poverty and human rights. 2008. Polity. Cambridge. 978-0745641430. 2nd. 9 March 2015.
  7. Mulligan, Erin R. "Paternalism and the Southern Hierarchy: How Slaves Defined Antebellum Southern Women", Armstrong Undergraduate Journal of History 2, no. 2, August 2012.
  8. Web site: The Excuse of Paternalism in the Antebellum South: Ideology or Practice?.
  9. Book: Johnson, Walter. Walter Johnson (historian). February 2000. Soul by Soul: Life Inside the Antebellum Slave Market. Harvard University Press. 18. 978-0674005396.