Mathematics Explained
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, theories and theorems that are developed and proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many areas of mathematics, which include number theory (the study of numbers), algebra (the study of formulas and related structures), geometry (the study of shapes and spaces that contain them), analysis (the study of continuous changes), and set theory (presently used as a foundation for all mathematics).
Mathematics involves the description and manipulation of abstract objects that consist of either abstractions from nature orin modern mathematicspurely abstract entities that are stipulated to have certain properties, called axioms. Mathematics uses pure reason to prove properties of objects, a proof consisting of a succession of applications of deductive rules to already established results. These results include previously proved theorems, axioms, andin case of abstraction from naturesome basic properties that are considered true starting points of the theory under consideration.[1]
Mathematics is essential in the natural sciences, engineering, medicine, finance, computer science, and the social sciences. Although mathematics is extensively used for modeling phenomena, the fundamental truths of mathematics are independent of any scientific experimentation. Some areas of mathematics, such as statistics and game theory, are developed in close correlation with their applications and are often grouped under applied mathematics. Other areas are developed independently from any application (and are therefore called pure mathematics) but often later find practical applications.
Historically, the concept of a proof and its associated mathematical rigour first appeared in Greek mathematics, most notably in Euclid's Elements.[2] Since its beginning, mathematics was primarily divided into geometry and arithmetic (the manipulation of natural numbers and fractions), until the 16th and 17th centuries, when algebra and infinitesimal calculus were introduced as new fields. Since then, the interaction between mathematical innovations and scientific discoveries has led to a correlated increase in the development of both.[3] At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis of mathematics led to the systematization of the axiomatic method,[4] which heralded a dramatic increase in the number of mathematical areas and their fields of application. The contemporary Mathematics Subject Classification lists more than sixty first-level areas of mathematics.
Etymology
The word mathematics comes from Ancient Greek máthēma (), meaning "that which is learnt",[5] "what one gets to know", hence also "study" and "science". The word came to have the narrower and more technical meaning of "mathematical study" even in Classical times. Its adjective is mathēmatikós (Greek, Ancient (to 1453);: μαθηματικός), meaning "related to learning" or "studious", which likewise further came to mean "mathematical".[6] In particular, mathēmatikḗ tékhnē (Greek, Ancient (to 1453);: μαθηματικὴ τέχνη; Latin: ars mathematica) meant "the mathematical art".
Similarly, one of the two main schools of thought in Pythagoreanism was known as the mathēmatikoi (μαθηματικοί)which at the time meant "learners" rather than "mathematicians" in the modern sense. The Pythagoreans were likely the first to constrain the use of the word to just the study of arithmetic and geometry. By the time of Aristotle (384–322 BC) this meaning was fully established.[7]
In Latin and English, until around 1700, the term mathematics more commonly meant "astrology" (or sometimes "astronomy") rather than "mathematics"; the meaning gradually changed to its present one from about 1500 to 1800. This change has resulted in several mistranslations: For example, Saint Augustine's warning that Christians should beware of mathematici, meaning "astrologers", is sometimes mistranslated as a condemnation of mathematicians.[8]
The apparent plural form in English goes back to the Latin neuter plural Latin: mathematica (Cicero), based on the Greek plural ta mathēmatiká (Greek, Modern (1453-);: τὰ μαθηματικά) and means roughly "all things mathematical", although it is plausible that English borrowed only the adjective mathematic(al) and formed the noun mathematics anew, after the pattern of physics and metaphysics, inherited from Greek.[9] In English, the noun mathematics takes a singular verb. It is often shortened to maths[10] or, in North America, math.[11]
Areas of mathematics
Before the Renaissance, mathematics was divided into two main areas: arithmetic, regarding the manipulation of numbers, and geometry, regarding the study of shapes.[12] Some types of pseudoscience, such as numerology and astrology, were not then clearly distinguished from mathematics.[13]
During the Renaissance, two more areas appeared. Mathematical notation led to algebra which, roughly speaking, consists of the study and the manipulation of formulas. Calculus, consisting of the two subfields differential calculus and integral calculus, is the study of continuous functions, which model the typically nonlinear relationships between varying quantities, as represented by variables. This division into four main areasarithmetic, geometry, algebra, calculus[14] endured until the end of the 19th century. Areas such as celestial mechanics and solid mechanics were then studied by mathematicians, but now are considered as belonging to physics.[15] The subject of combinatorics has been studied for much of recorded history, yet did not become a separate branch of mathematics until the seventeenth century.[16]
At the end of the 19th century, the foundational crisis in mathematics and the resulting systematization of the axiomatic method led to an explosion of new areas of mathematics.[17] The 2020 Mathematics Subject Classification contains no less than first-level areas.[18] Some of these areas correspond to the older division, as is true regarding number theory (the modern name for higher arithmetic) and geometry. Several other first-level areas have "geometry" in their names or are otherwise commonly considered part of geometry. Algebra and calculus do not appear as first-level areas but are respectively split into several first-level areas. Other first-level areas emerged during the 20th century or had not previously been considered as mathematics, such as mathematical logic and foundations.[19]
Number theory
See main article: Number theory. Number theory began with the manipulation of numbers, that is, natural numbers
and later expanded to
integers
and
rational numbers
Number theory was once called arithmetic, but nowadays this term is mostly used for
numerical calculations.
[20] Number theory dates back to ancient
Babylon and probably China. Two prominent early number theorists were
Euclid of ancient Greece and
Diophantus of Alexandria.
[21] The modern study of number theory in its abstract form is largely attributed to
Pierre de Fermat and
Leonhard Euler. The field came to full fruition with the contributions of
Adrien-Marie Legendre and
Carl Friedrich Gauss.
[22] Many easily stated number problems have solutions that require sophisticated methods, often from across mathematics. A prominent example is Fermat's Last Theorem. This conjecture was stated in 1637 by Pierre de Fermat, but it was proved only in 1994 by Andrew Wiles, who used tools including scheme theory from algebraic geometry, category theory, and homological algebra.[23] Another example is Goldbach's conjecture, which asserts that every even integer greater than 2 is the sum of two prime numbers. Stated in 1742 by Christian Goldbach, it remains unproven despite considerable effort.[24]
Number theory includes several subareas, including analytic number theory, algebraic number theory, geometry of numbers (method oriented), diophantine equations, and transcendence theory (problem oriented).
Geometry
See main article: Geometry.
Geometry is one of the oldest branches of mathematics. It started with empirical recipes concerning shapes, such as lines, angles and circles, which were developed mainly for the needs of surveying and architecture, but has since blossomed out into many other subfields.[25]
A fundamental innovation was the ancient Greeks' introduction of the concept of proofs, which require that every assertion must be proved. For example, it is not sufficient to verify by measurement that, say, two lengths are equal; their equality must be proven via reasoning from previously accepted results (theorems) and a few basic statements. The basic statements are not subject to proof because they are self-evident (postulates), or are part of the definition of the subject of study (axioms). This principle, foundational for all mathematics, was first elaborated for geometry, and was systematized by Euclid around 300 BC in his book Elements.[26] [27]
The resulting Euclidean geometry is the study of shapes and their arrangements constructed from lines, planes and circles in the Euclidean plane (plane geometry) and the three-dimensional Euclidean space.
Euclidean geometry was developed without change of methods or scope until the 17th century, when René Descartes introduced what is now called Cartesian coordinates. This constituted a major change of paradigm: Instead of defining real numbers as lengths of line segments (see number line), it allowed the representation of points using their coordinates, which are numbers. Algebra (and later, calculus) can thus be used to solve geometrical problems. Geometry was split into two new subfields: synthetic geometry, which uses purely geometrical methods, and analytic geometry, which uses coordinates systemically.[28]
Analytic geometry allows the study of curves unrelated to circles and lines. Such curves can be defined as the graph of functions, the study of which led to differential geometry. They can also be defined as implicit equations, often polynomial equations (which spawned algebraic geometry). Analytic geometry also makes it possible to consider Euclidean spaces of higher than three dimensions.
In the 19th century, mathematicians discovered non-Euclidean geometries, which do not follow the parallel postulate. By questioning that postulate's truth, this discovery has been viewed as joining Russell's paradox in revealing the foundational crisis of mathematics. This aspect of the crisis was solved by systematizing the axiomatic method, and adopting that the truth of the chosen axioms is not a mathematical problem.[29] In turn, the axiomatic method allows for the study of various geometries obtained either by changing the axioms or by considering properties that do not change under specific transformations of the space.[30]
Today's subareas of geometry include:
- Projective geometry, introduced in the 16th century by Girard Desargues, extends Euclidean geometry by adding points at infinity at which parallel lines intersect. This simplifies many aspects of classical geometry by unifying the treatments for intersecting and parallel lines.
- Affine geometry, the study of properties relative to parallelism and independent from the concept of length.
- Differential geometry, the study of curves, surfaces, and their generalizations, which are defined using differentiable functions.
- Manifold theory, the study of shapes that are not necessarily embedded in a larger space.
- Riemannian geometry, the study of distance properties in curved spaces.
- Algebraic geometry, the study of curves, surfaces, and their generalizations, which are defined using polynomials.
- Topology, the study of properties that are kept under continuous deformations.
- Discrete geometry, the study of finite configurations in geometry.
- Convex geometry, the study of convex sets, which takes its importance from its applications in optimization.
- Complex geometry, the geometry obtained by replacing real numbers with complex numbers.
Algebra
Algebra is the art of manipulating equations and formulas. Diophantus (3rd century) and al-Khwarizmi (9th century) were the two main precursors of algebra.[31] Diophantus solved some equations involving unknown natural numbers by deducing new relations until he obtained the solution.[32] Al-Khwarizmi introduced systematic methods for transforming equations, such as moving a term from one side of an equation into the other side.[33] The term algebra is derived from the Arabic word al-jabr meaning 'the reunion of broken parts' that he used for naming one of these methods in the title of his main treatise.[34] [35]
Algebra became an area in its own right only with François Viète (1540–1603), who introduced the use of variables for representing unknown or unspecified numbers.[36] Variables allow mathematicians to describe the operations that have to be done on the numbers represented using mathematical formulas.[37]
Until the 19th century, algebra consisted mainly of the study of linear equations (presently linear algebra), and polynomial equations in a single unknown, which were called algebraic equations (a term still in use, although it may be ambiguous). During the 19th century, mathematicians began to use variables to represent things other than numbers (such as matrices, modular integers, and geometric transformations), on which generalizations of arithmetic operations are often valid. The concept of algebraic structure addresses this, consisting of a set whose elements are unspecified, of operations acting on the elements of the set, and rules that these operations must follow. The scope of algebra thus grew to include the study of algebraic structures. This object of algebra was called modern algebra or abstract algebra, as established by the influence and works of Emmy Noether.[38]
Some types of algebraic structures have useful and often fundamental properties, in many areas of mathematics. Their study became autonomous parts of algebra, and include:
The study of types of algebraic structures as mathematical objects is the purpose of universal algebra and category theory.[39] The latter applies to every mathematical structure (not only algebraic ones). At its origin, it was introduced, together with homological algebra for allowing the algebraic study of non-algebraic objects such as topological spaces; this particular area of application is called algebraic topology.[40]
Calculus and analysis
See main article: Calculus and Mathematical analysis.
Calculus, formerly called infinitesimal calculus, was introduced independently and simultaneously by 17th-century mathematicians Newton and Leibniz.[41] It is fundamentally the study of the relationship of variables that depend on each other. Calculus was expanded in the 18th century by Euler with the introduction of the concept of a function and many other results.[42] Presently, "calculus" refers mainly to the elementary part of this theory, and "analysis" is commonly used for advanced parts.[43]
Analysis is further subdivided into real analysis, where variables represent real numbers, and complex analysis, where variables represent complex numbers. Analysis includes many subareas shared by other areas of mathematics which include:
Discrete mathematics
See main article: Discrete mathematics. Discrete mathematics, broadly speaking, is the study of individual, countable mathematical objects. An example is the set of all integers.[44] Because the objects of study here are discrete, the methods of calculus and mathematical analysis do not directly apply. Algorithmsespecially their implementation and computational complexityplay a major role in discrete mathematics.[45]
The four color theorem and optimal sphere packing were two major problems of discrete mathematics solved in the second half of the 20th century.[46] The P versus NP problem, which remains open to this day, is also important for discrete mathematics, since its solution would potentially impact a large number of computationally difficult problems.[47]
Discrete mathematics includes:
- Combinatorics, the art of enumerating mathematical objects that satisfy some given constraints. Originally, these objects were elements or subsets of a given set; this has been extended to various objects, which establishes a strong link between combinatorics and other parts of discrete mathematics. For example, discrete geometry includes counting configurations of geometric shapes
- Graph theory and hypergraphs
- Coding theory, including error correcting codes and a part of cryptography
- Matroid theory
- Discrete geometry
- Discrete probability distributions
- Game theory (although continuous games are also studied, most common games, such as chess and poker are discrete)
- Discrete optimization, including combinatorial optimization, integer programming, constraint programming
Mathematical logic and set theory
See main article: Mathematical logic and Set theory.
The two subjects of mathematical logic and set theory have belonged to mathematics since the end of the 19th century.[48] [49] Before this period, sets were not considered to be mathematical objects, and logic, although used for mathematical proofs, belonged to philosophy and was not specifically studied by mathematicians.[50]
Before Cantor's study of infinite sets, mathematicians were reluctant to consider actually infinite collections, and considered infinity to be the result of endless enumeration. Cantor's work offended many mathematicians not only by considering actually infinite sets[51] but by showing that this implies different sizes of infinity, per Cantor's diagonal argument. This led to the controversy over Cantor's set theory.[52] In the same period, various areas of mathematics concluded the former intuitive definitions of the basic mathematical objects were insufficient for ensuring mathematical rigour.[53]
This became the foundational crisis of mathematics.[54] It was eventually solved in mainstream mathematics by systematizing the axiomatic method inside a formalized set theory. Roughly speaking, each mathematical object is defined by the set of all similar objects and the properties that these objects must have. For example, in Peano arithmetic, the natural numbers are defined by "zero is a number", "each number has a unique successor", "each number but zero has a unique predecessor", and some rules of reasoning.[55] This mathematical abstraction from reality is embodied in the modern philosophy of formalism, as founded by David Hilbert around 1910.[56]
The "nature" of the objects defined this way is a philosophical problem that mathematicians leave to philosophers, even if many mathematicians have opinions on this nature, and use their opinionsometimes called "intuition"to guide their study and proofs. The approach allows considering "logics" (that is, sets of allowed deducing rules), theorems, proofs, etc. as mathematical objects, and to prove theorems about them. For example, Gödel's incompleteness theorems assert, roughly speaking that, in every consistent formal system that contains the natural numbers, there are theorems that are true (that is provable in a stronger system), but not provable inside the system.[57] This approach to the foundations of mathematics was challenged during the first half of the 20th century by mathematicians led by Brouwer, who promoted intuitionistic logic, which explicitly lacks the law of excluded middle.[58] [59]
These problems and debates led to a wide expansion of mathematical logic, with subareas such as model theory (modeling some logical theories inside other theories), proof theory, type theory, computability theory and computational complexity theory. Although these aspects of mathematical logic were introduced before the rise of computers, their use in compiler design, formal verification, program analysis, proof assistants and other aspects of computer science, contributed in turn to the expansion of these logical theories.[60]
Statistics and other decision sciences
See main article: Statistics and Probability theory.
The field of statistics is a mathematical application that is employed for the collection and processing of data samples, using procedures based on mathematical methods especially probability theory. Statisticians generate data with random sampling or randomized experiments.[61]
Statistical theory studies decision problems such as minimizing the risk (expected loss) of a statistical action, such as using a procedure in, for example, parameter estimation, hypothesis testing, and selecting the best. In these traditional areas of mathematical statistics, a statistical-decision problem is formulated by minimizing an objective function, like expected loss or cost, under specific constraints. For example, designing a survey often involves minimizing the cost of estimating a population mean with a given level of confidence.[62] Because of its use of optimization, the mathematical theory of statistics overlaps with other decision sciences, such as operations research, control theory, and mathematical economics.
Computational mathematics
See main article: Computational mathematics. Computational mathematics is the study of mathematical problems that are typically too large for human, numerical capacity.[63] [64] Numerical analysis studies methods for problems in analysis using functional analysis and approximation theory; numerical analysis broadly includes the study of approximation and discretization with special focus on rounding errors.[65] Numerical analysis and, more broadly, scientific computing also study non-analytic topics of mathematical science, especially algorithmic-matrix-and-graph theory. Other areas of computational mathematics include computer algebra and symbolic computation.
History
See main article: History of mathematics.
Ancient
In addition to recognizing how to count physical objects, prehistoric peoples may have also known how to count abstract quantities, like timedays, seasons, or years.[66] [67] Evidence for more complex mathematics does not appear until around 3000 , when the Babylonians and Egyptians began using arithmetic, algebra, and geometry for taxation and other financial calculations, for building and construction, and for astronomy. The oldest mathematical texts from Mesopotamia and Egypt are from 2000 to 1800 BC.[68] Many early texts mention Pythagorean triples and so, by inference, the Pythagorean theorem seems to be the most ancient and widespread mathematical concept after basic arithmetic and geometry. It is in Babylonian mathematics that elementary arithmetic (addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division) first appear in the archaeological record. The Babylonians also possessed a place-value system and used a sexagesimal numeral system which is still in use today for measuring angles and time.
In the 6th century BC, Greek mathematics began to emerge as a distinct discipline and some Ancient Greeks such as the Pythagoreans appeared to have considered it a subject in its own right.[69] Around 300 BC, Euclid organized mathematical knowledge by way of postulates and first principles, which evolved into the axiomatic method that is used in mathematics today, consisting of definition, axiom, theorem, and proof.[70] His book, Elements, is widely considered the most successful and influential textbook of all time. The greatest mathematician of antiquity is often held to be Archimedes of Syracuse. He developed formulas for calculating the surface area and volume of solids of revolution and used the method of exhaustion to calculate the area under the arc of a parabola with the summation of an infinite series, in a manner not too dissimilar from modern calculus. Other notable achievements of Greek mathematics are conic sections (Apollonius of Perga, 3rd century BC), trigonometry (Hipparchus of Nicaea, 2nd century BC), and the beginnings of algebra (Diophantus, 3rd century AD).The Hindu–Arabic numeral system and the rules for the use of its operations, in use throughout the world today, evolved over the course of the first millennium AD in India and were transmitted to the Western world via Islamic mathematics.[71] Other notable developments of Indian mathematics include the modern definition and approximation of sine and cosine, and an early form of infinite series.[72] [73]
Medieval and later
During the Golden Age of Islam, especially during the 9th and 10th centuries, mathematics saw many important innovations building on Greek mathematics. The most notable achievement of Islamic mathematics was the development of algebra. Other achievements of the Islamic period include advances in spherical trigonometry and the addition of the decimal point to the Arabic numeral system.[74] Many notable mathematicians from this period were Persian, such as Al-Khwarizmi, Omar Khayyam and Sharaf al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī.[75] The Greek and Arabic mathematical texts were in turn translated to Latin during the Middle Ages and made available in Europe.[76]
During the early modern period, mathematics began to develop at an accelerating pace in Western Europe, with innovations that revolutionized mathematics, such as the introduction of variables and symbolic notation by François Viète (1540–1603), the introduction of logarithms by John Napier in 1614, which greatly simplified numerical calculations, especially for astronomy and marine navigation, the introduction of coordinates by René Descartes (1596–1650) for reducing geometry to algebra, and the development of calculus by Isaac Newton (1643–1727) and Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716). Leonhard Euler (1707–1783), the most notable mathematician of the 18th century, unified these innovations into a single corpus with a standardized terminology, and completed them with the discovery and the proof of numerous theorems.[77]
Perhaps the foremost mathematician of the 19th century was the German mathematician Carl Gauss, who made numerous contributions to fields such as algebra, analysis, differential geometry, matrix theory, number theory, and statistics.[78] In the early 20th century, Kurt Gödel transformed mathematics by publishing his incompleteness theorems, which show in part that any consistent axiomatic systemif powerful enough to describe arithmeticwill contain true propositions that cannot be proved.
Mathematics has since been greatly extended, and there has been a fruitful interaction between mathematics and science, to the benefit of both. Mathematical discoveries continue to be made to this very day. According to Mikhail B. Sevryuk, in the January 2006 issue of the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, "The number of papers and books included in the Mathematical Reviews database since 1940 (the first year of operation of MR) is now more than 1.9 million, and more than 75 thousand items are added to the database each year. The overwhelming majority of works in this ocean contain new mathematical theorems and their proofs."
Symbolic notation and terminology
See main article: Mathematical notation and Language of mathematics. Mathematical notation is widely used in science and engineering for representing complex concepts and properties in a concise, unambiguous, and accurate way. This notation consists of symbols used for representing operations,, unspecified numbers, relations and any other mathematical objects, and then assembling them into expressions and formulas.[79] More precisely, numbers and other mathematical objects are represented by symbols called variables, which are generally Latin or Greek letters, and often include subscripts. Operation and relations are generally represented by specific symbols or glyphs,[80] such as (plus), (multiplication), (integral), (equal), and (less than).[81] All these symbols are generally grouped according to specific rules to form expressions and formulas.[82] Normally, expressions and formulas do not appear alone, but are included in sentences of the current language, where expressions play the role of noun phrases and formulas play the role of clauses.
Mathematics has developed a rich terminology covering a broad range of fields that study the properties of various abstract, idealized objects and how they interact. It is based on rigorous definitions that provide a standard foundation for communication. An axiom or postulate is a mathematical statement that is taken to be true without need of proof. If a mathematical statement has yet to be proven (or disproven), it is termed a conjecture. Through a series of rigorous arguments employing deductive reasoning, a statement that is proven to be true becomes a theorem. A specialized theorem that is mainly used to prove another theorem is called a lemma. A proven instance that forms part of a more general finding is termed a corollary.[83]
Numerous technical terms used in mathematics are neologisms, such as polynomial and homeomorphism.[84] Other technical terms are words of the common language that are used in an accurate meaning that may differ slightly from their common meaning. For example, in mathematics, "or" means "one, the other or both", while, in common language, it is either ambiguous or means "one or the other but not both" (in mathematics, the latter is called "exclusive or"). Finally, many mathematical terms are common words that are used with a completely different meaning.[85] This may lead to sentences that are correct and true mathematical assertions, but appear to be nonsense to people who do not have the required background. For example, "every free module is flat" and "a field is always a ring".
Relationship with sciences
Mathematics is used in most sciences for modeling phenomena, which then allows predictions to be made from experimental laws.[86] The independence of mathematical truth from any experimentation implies that the accuracy of such predictions depends only on the adequacy of the model.[87] Inaccurate predictions, rather than being caused by invalid mathematical concepts, imply the need to change the mathematical model used.[88] For example, the perihelion precession of Mercury could only be explained after the emergence of Einstein's general relativity, which replaced Newton's law of gravitation as a better mathematical model.[89]
There is still a philosophical debate whether mathematics is a science. However, in practice, mathematicians are typically grouped with scientists, and mathematics shares much in common with the physical sciences. Like them, it is falsifiable, which means in mathematics that, if a result or a theory is wrong, this can be proved by providing a counterexample. Similarly as in science, theories and results (theorems) are often obtained from experimentation.[90] In mathematics, the experimentation may consist of computation on selected examples or of the study of figures or other representations of mathematical objects (often mind representations without physical support). For example, when asked how he came about his theorems, Gauss once replied "durch planmässiges Tattonieren" (through systematic experimentation).[91] However, some authors emphasize that mathematics differs from the modern notion of science by not on empirical evidence.[92] [93] [94] [95]
Pure and applied mathematics
See main article: Applied mathematics and Pure mathematics.
Until the 19th century, the development of mathematics in the West was mainly motivated by the needs of technology and science, and there was no clear distinction between pure and applied mathematics.[96] For example, the natural numbers and arithmetic were introduced for the need of counting, and geometry was motivated by surveying, architecture and astronomy. Later, Isaac Newton introduced infinitesimal calculus for explaining the movement of the planets with his law of gravitation. Moreover, most mathematicians were also scientists, and many scientists were also mathematicians.[97] However, a notable exception occurred with the tradition of pure mathematics in Ancient Greece.[98] The problem of integer factorization, for example, which goes back to Euclid in 300 BC, had no practical application before its use in the RSA cryptosystem, now widely used for the security of computer networks.[99]
In the 19th century, mathematicians such as Karl Weierstrass and Richard Dedekind increasingly focused their research on internal problems, that is, pure mathematics.[100] This led to split mathematics into pure mathematics and applied mathematics, the latter being often considered as having a lower value among mathematical purists. However, the lines between the two are frequently blurred.[101]
The aftermath of World War II led to a surge in the development of applied mathematics in the US and elsewhere.[102] [103] Many of the theories developed for applications were found interesting from the point of view of pure mathematics, and many results of pure mathematics were shown to have applications outside mathematics; in turn, the study of these applications may give new insights on the "pure theory".[104] [105]
An example of the first case is the theory of distributions, introduced by Laurent Schwartz for validating computations done in quantum mechanics, which became immediately an important tool of (pure) mathematical analysis.[106] An example of the second case is the decidability of the first-order theory of the real numbers, a problem of pure mathematics that was proved true by Alfred Tarski, with an algorithm that is impossible to implement because of a computational complexity that is much too high.[107] For getting an algorithm that can be implemented and can solve systems of polynomial equations and inequalities, George Collins introduced the cylindrical algebraic decomposition that became a fundamental tool in real algebraic geometry.[108]
In the present day, the distinction between pure and applied mathematics is more a question of personal research aim of mathematicians than a division of mathematics into broad areas.[109] [110] The Mathematics Subject Classification has a section for "general applied mathematics" but does not mention "pure mathematics". However, these terms are still used in names of some university departments, such as at the Faculty of Mathematics at the University of Cambridge.
Unreasonable effectiveness
The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics is a phenomenon that was named and first made explicit by physicist Eugene Wigner.[111] It is the fact that many mathematical theories (even the "purest") have applications outside their initial object. These applications may be completely outside their initial area of mathematics, and may concern physical phenomena that were completely unknown when the mathematical theory was introduced.[112] Examples of unexpected applications of mathematical theories can be found in many areas of mathematics.
A notable example is the prime factorization of natural numbers that was discovered more than 2,000 years before its common use for secure internet communications through the RSA cryptosystem.[113] A second historical example is the theory of ellipses. They were studied by the ancient Greek mathematicians as conic sections (that is, intersections of cones with planes). It is almost 2,000 years later that Johannes Kepler discovered that the trajectories of the planets are ellipses.[114]
In the 19th century, the internal development of geometry (pure mathematics) led to definition and study of non-Euclidean geometries, spaces of dimension higher than three and manifolds. At this time, these concepts seemed totally disconnected from the physical reality, but at the beginning of the 20th century, Albert Einstein developed the theory of relativity that uses fundamentally these concepts. In particular, spacetime of special relativity is a non-Euclidean space of dimension four, and spacetime of general relativity is a (curved) manifold of dimension four.[115] [116]
In both cases, the equations of the theories had unexplained solutions, which led to conjecture of the existence of an unknown
particle, and the search for these particles. In both cases, these particles were discovered a few years later by specific experiments.
[117] [118] Specific sciences
Physics
See main article: Relationship between mathematics and physics. Mathematics and physics have influenced each other over their modern history. Modern physics uses mathematics abundantly,[119] and is also considered to be the motivation of major mathematical developments.[120]
Computing
Computing is closely related to mathematics in several ways.[121] Theoretical computer science is considered to be mathematical in nature.[122] Communication technologies apply branches of mathematics that may be very old (e.g., arithmetic), especially with respect to transmission security, in cryptography and coding theory. Discrete mathematics is useful in many areas of computer science, such as complexity theory, information theory, and graph theory.[123] In 1998, the Kepler conjecture on sphere packing seemed to also be partially proven by computer.[124]
Biology and chemistry
See main article: Mathematical and theoretical biology and Mathematical chemistry. Biology uses probability extensively in fields such as ecology or neurobiology.[125] Most discussion of probability centers on the concept of evolutionary fitness. Ecology heavily uses modeling to simulate population dynamics,[126] study ecosystems such as the predator-prey model, measure pollution diffusion, or to assess climate change. The dynamics of a population can be modeled by coupled differential equations, such as the Lotka–Volterra equations.[127]
Statistical hypothesis testing, is run on data from clinical trials to determine whether a new treatment works.[128] Since the start of the 20th century, chemistry has used computing to model molecules in three dimensions.[129]
Earth sciences
See main article: Geomathematics. Structural geology and climatology use probabilistic models to predict the risk of natural catastrophes.[130] Similarly, meteorology, oceanography, and planetology also use mathematics due to their heavy use of models.[131] [132] [133]
Social sciences
Areas of mathematics used in the social sciences include probability/statistics and differential equations. These are used in linguistics, economics, sociology,[134] and psychology.Often the fundamental postulate of mathematical economics is that of the rational individual actor – Homo economicus .[135] In this model, the individual seeks to maximize their self-interest, and always makes optimal choices using perfect information.[136] This atomistic view of economics allows it to relatively easily mathematize its thinking, because individual calculations are transposed into mathematical calculations. Such mathematical modeling allows one to probe economic mechanisms. Some reject or criticise the concept of Homo economicus. Economists note that real people have limited information, make poor choices and care about fairness, altruism, not just personal gain.[137]
Without mathematical modeling, it is hard to go beyond statistical observations or untestable speculation. Mathematical modeling allows economists to create structured frameworks to test hypotheses and analyze complex interactions. Models provide clarity and precision, enabling the translation of theoretical concepts into quantifiable predictions that can be tested against real-world data.[138]
At the start of the 20th century, there was a development to express historical movements in formulas. In 1922, Nikolai Kondratiev discerned the ~50-year-long Kondratiev cycle, which explains phases of economic growth or crisis.[139] Towards the end of the 19th century, mathematicians extended their analysis into geopolitics.[140] Peter Turchin developed cliodynamics since the 1990s.[141]
Mathematization of the social sciences is not without risk. In the controversial book Fashionable Nonsense (1997), Sokal and Bricmont denounced the unfounded or abusive use of scientific terminology, particularly from mathematics or physics, in the social sciences.[142] The study of complex systems (evolution of unemployment, business capital, demographic evolution of a population, etc.) uses mathematical knowledge. However, the choice of counting criteria, particularly for unemployment, or of models, can be subject to controversy.[143] [144]
Relationship with astrology and esotericism
Some renowned mathematicians have also been considered to be renowned astrologists; for example, Ptolemy, Arab astronomers, Regiomantus, Cardano, Kepler, or John Dee. In the Middle Ages, astrology was considered a science that included mathematics. In his encyclopedia, Theodor Zwinger wrote that astrology was a mathematical science that studied the "active movement of bodies as they act on other bodies". He reserved to mathematics the need to "calculate with probability the influences [of stars]" to foresee their "conjunctions and oppositions".[145] As of 2023, astrology is no longer considered a science, but pseudoscience.[146]
Philosophy
See main article: Philosophy of mathematics.
Reality
The connection between mathematics and material reality has led to philosophical debates since at least the time of Pythagoras. The ancient philosopher Plato argued that abstractions that reflect material reality have themselves a reality that exists outside space and time. As a result, the philosophical view that mathematical objects somehow exist on their own in abstraction is often referred to as Platonism. Independently of their possible philosophical opinions, modern mathematicians may be generally considered as Platonists, since they think of and talk of their objects of study as real objects.[147]
Armand Borel summarized this view of mathematics reality as follows, and provided quotations of G. H. Hardy, Charles Hermite, Henri Poincaré and Albert Einstein that support his views.
Nevertheless, Platonism and the concurrent views on abstraction do not explain the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics.[148]
Proposed definitions
See main article: Definitions of mathematics.
There is no general consensus about a definition of mathematics or its epistemological statusthat is, its place among other human activities.[149] [150] A great many professional mathematicians take no interest in a definition of mathematics, or consider it undefinable. There is not even consensus on whether mathematics is an art or a science. Some just say, "mathematics is what mathematicians do". This makes sense, as there is a strong consensus among them about what is mathematics and what is not. Most proposed definitions try to define mathematics by its object of study.[151]
Aristotle defined mathematics as "the science of quantity" and this definition prevailed until the 18th century. However, Aristotle also noted a focus on quantity alone may not distinguish mathematics from sciences like physics; in his view, abstraction and studying quantity as a property "separable in thought" from real instances set mathematics apart.[152] In the 19th century, when mathematicians began to address topicssuch as infinite setswhich have no clear-cut relation to physical reality, a variety of new definitions were given.[153] With the large number of new areas of mathematics that appeared since the beginning of the 20th century and continue to appear, defining mathematics by this object of study becomes an impossible task. For example, in lieu of a definition, Saunders Mac Lane in Mathematics, form and function summarizes the basics of several areas of mathematics, emphasizing their inter-connectedness, and observes:[154]
Another approach for defining mathematics is to use its methods. So, an area of study can be qualified as mathematics as soon as one can prove theoremsassertions whose validity relies on a proof, that is, a purely-logical deduction.[155] Others take the perspective that mathematics is an investigation of axiomatic set theory, as this study is now a foundational discipline for much of modern mathematics.[156]
Rigor
See also: Logic. Mathematical reasoning requires rigor. This means that the definitions must be absolutely unambiguous and the proofs must be reducible to a succession of applications of inference rules, without any use of empirical evidence and intuition.[157] Rigorous reasoning is not specific to mathematics, but, in mathematics, the standard of rigor is much higher than elsewhere. Despite mathematics' concision, rigorous proofs can require hundreds of pages to express, such as the 255-page Feit–Thompson theorem. The emergence of computer-assisted proofs has allowed proof lengths to further expand,[158] The result of this trend is a philosophy of the quasi-empiricist proof that can not be considered infallible, but has a probability attached to it.
The concept of rigor in mathematics dates back to ancient Greece, where their society encouraged logical, deductive reasoning. However, this rigorous approach would tend to discourage exploration of new approaches, such as irrational numbers and concepts of infinity. The method of demonstrating rigorous proof was enhanced in the sixteenth century through the use of symbolic notation. In the 18th century, social transition led to mathematicians earning their keep through teaching, which led to more careful thinking about the underlying concepts of mathematics. This produced more rigorous approaches, while transitioning from geometric methods to algebraic and then arithmetic proofs.
At the end of the 19th century, it appeared that the definitions of the basic concepts of mathematics were not accurate enough for avoiding paradoxes (non-Euclidean geometries and Weierstrass function) and contradictions (Russell's paradox). This was solved by the inclusion of axioms with the apodictic inference rules of mathematical theories; the re-introduction of axiomatic method pioneered by the ancient Greeks. It results that "rigor" is no more a relevant concept in mathematics, as a proof is either correct or erroneous, and a "rigorous proof" is simply a pleonasm. Where a special concept of rigor comes into play is in the socialized aspects of a proof, wherein it may be demonstrably refuted by other mathematicians. After a proof has been accepted for many years or even decades, it can then be considered as reliable.[159]
Nevertheless, the concept of "rigor" may remain useful for teaching to beginners what is a mathematical proof.[160]
Training and practice
Education
See main article: Mathematics education. Mathematics has a remarkable ability to cross cultural boundaries and time periods. As a human activity, the practice of mathematics has a social side, which includes education, careers, recognition, popularization, and so on. In education, mathematics is a core part of the curriculum and forms an important element of the STEM academic disciplines. Prominent careers for professional mathematicians include math teacher or professor, statistician, actuary, financial analyst, economist, accountant, commodity trader, or computer consultant.[161]
Archaeological evidence shows that instruction in mathematics occurred as early as the second millennium BCE in ancient Babylonia.[162] Comparable evidence has been unearthed for scribal mathematics training in the ancient Near East and then for the Greco-Roman world starting around 300 BCE.[163] The oldest known mathematics textbook is the Rhind papyrus, dated from in Egypt.[164] Due to a scarcity of books, mathematical teachings in ancient India were communicated using memorized oral tradition since the Vedic period .[165] In Imperial China during the Tang dynasty (618–907 CE), a mathematics curriculum was adopted for the civil service exam to join the state bureaucracy.[166]
Following the Dark Ages, mathematics education in Europe was provided by religious schools as part of the Quadrivium. Formal instruction in pedagogy began with Jesuit schools in the 16th and 17th century. Most mathematical curriculum remained at a basic and practical level until the nineteenth century, when it began to flourish in France and Germany. The oldest journal addressing instruction in mathematics was L'Enseignement Mathématique, which began publication in 1899.[167] The Western advancements in science and technology led to the establishment of centralized education systems in many nation-states, with mathematics as a core componentinitially for its military applications.[168] While the content of courses varies, in the present day nearly all countries teach mathematics to students for significant amounts of time.[169]
During school, mathematical capabilities and positive expectations have a strong association with career interest in the field. Extrinsic factors such as feedback motivation by teachers, parents, and peer groups can influence the level of interest in mathematics.[170] Some students studying math may develop an apprehension or fear about their performance in the subject. This is known as math anxiety or math phobia, and is considered the most prominent of the disorders impacting academic performance. Math anxiety can develop due to various factors such as parental and teacher attitudes, social stereotypes, and personal traits. Help to counteract the anxiety can come from changes in instructional approaches, by interactions with parents and teachers, and by tailored treatments for the individual.[171]
Psychology (aesthetic, creativity and intuition)
The validity of a mathematical theorem relies only on the rigor of its proof, which could theoretically be done automatically by a computer program. This does not mean that there is no place for creativity in a mathematical work. On the contrary, many important mathematical results (theorems) are solutions of problems that other mathematicians failed to solve, and the invention of a way for solving them may be a fundamental way of the solving process.[172] [173] An extreme example is Apery's theorem: Roger Apery provided only the ideas for a proof, and the formal proof was given only several months later by three other mathematicians.[174]
Creativity and rigor are not the only psychological aspects of the activity of mathematicians. Some mathematicians can see their activity as a game, more specifically as solving puzzles.[175] This aspect of mathematical activity is emphasized in recreational mathematics.
Mathematicians can find an aesthetic value to mathematics. Like beauty, it is hard to define, it is commonly related to elegance, which involves qualities like simplicity, symmetry, completeness, and generality. G. H. Hardy in A Mathematician's Apology expressed the belief that the aesthetic considerations are, in themselves, sufficient to justify the study of pure mathematics. He also identified other criteria such as significance, unexpectedness, and inevitability, which contribute to mathematical aesthetic.[176] Paul Erdős expressed this sentiment more ironically by speaking of "The Book", a supposed divine collection of the most beautiful proofs. The 1998 book Proofs from THE BOOK, inspired by Erdős, is a collection of particularly succinct and revelatory mathematical arguments. Some examples of particularly elegant results included are Euclid's proof that there are infinitely many prime numbers and the fast Fourier transform for harmonic analysis.[177]
Some feel that to consider mathematics a science is to downplay its artistry and history in the seven traditional liberal arts.[178] One way this difference of viewpoint plays out is in the philosophical debate as to whether mathematical results are created (as in art) or discovered (as in science).[179] The popularity of recreational mathematics is another sign of the pleasure many find in solving mathematical questions.
Cultural impact
Artistic expression
See main article: Mathematics and art. Notes that sound well together to a Western ear are sounds whose fundamental frequencies of vibration are in simple ratios. For example, an octave doubles the frequency and a perfect fifth multiplies it by
.
[180] [181] Humans, as well as some other animals, find symmetric patterns to be more beautiful.[182] Mathematically, the symmetries of an object form a group known as the symmetry group.[183] For example, the group underlying mirror symmetry is the cyclic group of two elements,
. A Rorschach test is a figure invariant by this symmetry,
[184] as are butterfly and animal bodies more generally (at least on the surface).
[185] Waves on the sea surface possess translation symmetry: moving one's viewpoint by the distance between wave crests does not change one's view of the sea.
[186] Fractals possess
self-similarity.
[187] [188] Popularization
See main article: Popular mathematics. Popular mathematics is the act of presenting mathematics without technical terms.[189] Presenting mathematics may be hard since the general public suffers from mathematical anxiety and mathematical objects are highly abstract.[190] However, popular mathematics writing can overcome this by using applications or cultural links.[191] Despite this, mathematics is rarely the topic of popularization in printed or televised media.
Awards and prize problems
See main article: category and Mathematics awards.
The most prestigious award in mathematics is the Fields Medal, established in 1936 and awarded every four years (except around World War II) to up to four individuals.[192] [193] It is considered the mathematical equivalent of the Nobel Prize.
Other prestigious mathematics awards include:[194]
A famous list of 23 open problems, called "Hilbert's problems", was compiled in 1900 by German mathematician David Hilbert.[202] This list has achieved great celebrity among mathematicians,[203] and at least thirteen of the problems (depending how some are interpreted) have been solved.
A new list of seven important problems, titled the "Millennium Prize Problems", was published in 2000. Only one of them, the Riemann hypothesis, duplicates one of Hilbert's problems. A solution to any of these problems carries a 1 million dollar reward.[204] To date, only one of these problems, the Poincaré conjecture, has been solved by the Russian mathematician Grigori Perelman.[205]
See also
References
Sources
- Book: Bouleau, Nicolas . Philosophie des mathématiques et de la modélisation: Du chercheur à l'ingénieur . L'Harmattan . 1999 . 978-2-7384-8125-2.
- Book: Boyer . Carl Benjamin . Carl Benjamin Boyer . A History of Mathematics . 1991 . . New York . 978-0-471-54397-8 . 2nd . registration .
- Book: Eves, Howard . Howard Eves . An Introduction to the History of Mathematics . 6th . Saunders . 1990 . 978-0-03-029558-4 . none.
- Book: Kleiner, Israel . Israel . Kleiner . Israel Kleiner (mathematician) . 2007 . [{{GBurl|id=RTLRBK-wj6wC}} A History of Abstract Algebra ]. Springer Science & Business Media . 10.1007/978-0-8176-4685-1 . 978-0-8176-4684-4 . 2007932362 . 76935733 . 117392219 . February 8, 2024.
- Book: Kline, Morris . Morris Kline . Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times . registration . New York . Oxford University Press . 1990 . 978-0-19-506135-2 .
- Monastyrsky . Michael . Some Trends in Modern Mathematics and the Fields Medal . 2001 . CMS – Notes – de la SMC . 33 . 2–3 . Canadian Mathematical Society . July 28, 2006 . August 13, 2006 . https://web.archive.org/web/20060813224844/http://www.fields.utoronto.ca/aboutus/FieldsMedal_Monastyrsky.pdf . live .
- Book: Oakley, Barbara . Barbara Oakley . A Mind For Numbers: How to Excel at Math and Science (Even If You Flunked Algebra) . 2014 . Penguin Random House . New York . registration . A Mind for Numbers. . 978-0-399-16524-5 . none .
- Peirce . Benjamin . Benjamin Peirce . 97–229 . [{{GBurl|id=De0GAAAAYAAJ|q=Peirce Benjamin Linear Associative Algebra|p=1}} Linear associative algebra ]. Charles Sanders Peirce . Charles Sanders . Peirce . Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C.S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph . American Journal of Mathematics . 4 . 1881 . Corrected, expanded, and annotated revision with an 1875 paper by B. Peirce and annotations by his son, C. S. Peirce, of the 1872 lithograph ed. Google [{{GBurl|id=LQgPAAAAIAAJ|p=221}} Eprint] and as an extract, D. Van Nostrand, 1882, Google Eprint . 1–4 . 10.2307/2369153 . 2369153 . 2027/hvd.32044030622997 . free . November 17, 2020 . none . .
- Book: Peterson, Ivars . 1988 . The Mathematical Tourist: Snapshots of Modern Mathematics . W. H. Freeman and Company . 0-7167-1953-3 . 87033078 . 17202382.
- Book: Popper, Karl R. . Karl Popper . In Search of a Better World: Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years . New York . Routledge . On knowledge . 1995 . 978-0-415-13548-1 . 1992sbwl.book.....P . registration . none .
- Riehm . Carl . The Early History of the Fields Medal . Notices of the AMS . 49 . 7 . 778–782 . August 2002 . October 2, 2006 . October 26, 2006 . https://web.archive.org/web/20061026000014/http://www.ams.org/notices/200207/comm-riehm.pdf . live .
- Sevryuk . Mikhail B. . January 2006 . Book Reviews . . 43 . 1 . 101–109 . June 24, 2006 . 10.1090/S0273-0979-05-01069-4 . July 23, 2006 . https://web.archive.org/web/20060723082901/http://www.ams.org/bull/2006-43-01/S0273-0979-05-01069-4/S0273-0979-05-01069-4.pdf . live . free .
- Book: Whittle, Peter . Peter Whittle (mathematician) . Almost home . Frank Kelly (mathematician) . F.P. . Kelly . 1994 . Probability, statistics and optimisation: A Tribute to Peter Whittle . Chichester . John Wiley . 978-0-471-94829-2 . 1–28 . http://www.statslab.cam.ac.uk/History/2history.html#6._1966--72:_The_Churchill_Chair . previously "A realised path: The Cambridge Statistical Laboratory up to 1993 (revised 2002)" . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20131219080017/http://www.statslab.cam.ac.uk/History/2history.html#6._1966--72:_The_Churchill_Chair . December 19, 2013 .
Further reading
- Book: Benson, Donald C. . The Moment of Proof: Mathematical Epiphanies . Oxford University Press . 1999 . registration . 978-0-19-513919-8 . none.
- Book: Davis . Philip J. . Philip J. Davis . Hersh . Reuben . Reuben Hersh . The Mathematical Experience . Mariner Books . Boston; New York . Reprint . 1999 . 978-0-395-92968-1 . The Mathematical Experience . none. Available online (registration required).
- Book: Courant . Richard . Richard Courant . Robbins . Herbert . Herbert Robbins . What Is Mathematics?: An Elementary Approach to Ideas and Methods . New York . Oxford University Press . 2nd . 1996 . 978-0-19-510519-3 . registration . none.
- Book: Gullberg, Jan . Jan Gullberg . Mathematics: From the Birth of Numbers . registration . W.W. Norton & Company . 1997 . 978-0-393-04002-9 . none.
- Book: Hazewinkel . Michiel . Michiel Hazewinkel . Encyclopaedia of Mathematics . Kluwer Academic Publishers . 2000 . Encyclopaedia of Mathematics . none. – A translated and expanded version of a Soviet mathematics encyclopedia, in ten volumes. Also in paperback and on CD-ROM, and online. .
- Book: Hodgkin, Luke Howard . A History of Mathematics: From Mesopotamia to Modernity . Oxford University Press . 2005 . 978-0-19-152383-0.
- Book: Jourdain, Philip E. B. . Philip Jourdain . The Nature of Mathematics . The World of Mathematics . James R. Newman . Dover Publications . 2003 . 978-0-486-43268-7 . none.
- Book: Pappas . Theoni . Theoni Pappas . The Joy Of Mathematics . 1986 . Wide World Publishing . San Carlos, California . 978-0-933174-65-8 . registration . none.
- Book: Waltershausen, Wolfgang Sartorius von . Wolfgang Sartorius von Waltershausen . Gauss zum Gedächtniss . 1965 . 1856 . Sändig Reprint Verlag H. R. Wohlwend . 978-3-253-01702-5 . no.
Notes and References
- Book: Hipólito, Inês Viegas . Kanzian . Christian . Mitterer . Josef . Josef Mitterer . Neges . Katharina . August 9–15, 2015 . Abstract Cognition and the Nature of Mathematical Proof . 132–134 . Realismus – Relativismus – Konstruktivismus: Beiträge des 38. Internationalen Wittgenstein Symposiums . Realism – Relativism – Constructivism: Contributions of the 38th International Wittgenstein Symposium . 23 . de, en . Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society . Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria . 1022-3398 . 236026294 . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221107221937/https://www.alws.at/alws/wp-content/uploads/2018/06/papers-2015.pdf#page=133 . November 7, 2022 . January 17, 2024. (at ResearchGate)
- Web site: Wise . David . Eudoxus' Influence on Euclid's Elements with a close look at The Method of Exhaustion. . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20190601004355/http://jwilson.coe.uga.edu/emt668/EMAT6680.F99/Wise/essay7/essay7.htm . June 1, 2019 . January 18, 2024.
- Alexander . Amir . Amir Alexander . September 2011 . The Skeleton in the Closet: Should Historians of Science Care about the History of Mathematics? . Isis . 102 . 3 . 475–480 . 10.1086/661620 . 0021-1753 . 2884913 . 22073771 . 21629993.
- Kleiner . Israel . Israel Kleiner (mathematician) . December 1991 . Rigor and Proof in Mathematics: A Historical Perspective . Mathematics Magazine . Taylor & Francis, Ltd. . 64 . 5 . 291–314 . 10.1080/0025570X.1991.11977625 . 2690647 . 0025-570X . 1930-0980 . 47003192 . 1141557 . 1756877 . 7787171.
- Encyclopedia: Harper . Douglas . March 28, 2019 . Mathematic (n.) . . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20130307093926/http://etymonline.com/index.php?term=mathematic&allowed_in_frame=0 . March 7, 2013 . January 25, 2024.
- Encyclopedia: Harper . Douglas . December 22, 2018 . Mathematical (adj.) . . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221126170916/https://www.etymonline.com/word/mathematical . November 26, 2022 . January 25, 2024.
- Perisho . Margaret W. . Spring 1965 . The Etymology of Mathematical Terms . . 4 . 2 . 62–66 . 0031-952X . 24338341 . 58015848 . 1762376.
- Book: Boas, Ralph P. . Ralph P. Boas Jr. . Alexanderson . Gerald L. . Mugler . Dale H. . 1995 . What Augustine Didn't Say About Mathematicians . 257 . Lion Hunting and Other Mathematical Pursuits: A Collection of Mathematics, Verse, and Stories . . 978-0-88385-323-8 . 94078313 . 633018890.
- The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology, Oxford English Dictionary, sub "mathematics", "mathematic", "mathematics".
- Web site: Maths (Noun) . . . January 25, 2024.
- Web site: Math (Noun³) . . . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20200404201407/http://oed.com/view/Entry/114982 . April 4, 2020 . January 25, 2024.
- Book: Bell, E. T. . Eric Temple Bell . 1945 . 1940 . General Prospectus . The Development of Mathematics . 2nd . 978-0-486-27239-9 . 45010599 . 523284 . 3 . Dover Publications . ... mathematics has come down to the present by the two main streams of number and form. The first carried along arithmetic and algebra, the second, geometry..
- Book: Tiwari, Sarju . 1992 . A Mirror of Civilization . Mathematics in History, Culture, Philosophy, and Science . 1st . 27 . Mittal Publications . New Delhi, India . 978-81-7099-404-6 . 92909575 . 28115124 . It is unfortunate that two curses of mathematics--Numerology and Astrology were also born with it and have been more acceptable to the masses than mathematics itself..
- Book: Restivo, Sal . Sal Restivo . Bunge . Mario . Mario Bunge . 1992 . Mathematics from the Ground Up . Mathematics in Society and History . 14 . Episteme . 20 . . 0-7923-1765-3 . 25709270 . 92013695.
- Book: Musielak, Dora . Dora Musielak . 2022 . Leonhard Euler and the Foundations of Celestial Mechanics . History of Physics . . 10.1007/978-3-031-12322-1 . 978-3-031-12321-4 . 253240718 . 2730-7549 . 2730-7557 . 1332780664.
- May 1979 . Biggs . N. L. . The roots of combinatorics . Historia Mathematica . 6 . 2 . 109–136 . 10.1016/0315-0860(79)90074-0 . free . 0315-0860 . 1090-249X . 75642280 . 2240703.
- Web site: Warner . Evan . Splash Talk: The Foundational Crisis of Mathematics . . dead . https://web.archive.org/web/20230322165544/https://www.math.columbia.edu/~warner/notes/SplashTalk.pdf . March 22, 2023 . February 3, 2024.
- Dunne . Edward . Hulek . Klaus . Klaus Hulek . March 2020 . Mathematics Subject Classification 2020 . Notices of the American Mathematical Society . 67 . 3 . 410–411 . 10.1090/noti2052 . free . 0002-9920 . 1088-9477 . sf77000404 . 1480366 . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20210803203928/https://www.ams.org/journals/notices/202003/rnoti-p410.pdf . August 3, 2021 . February 3, 2024 . The new MSC contains 63 two-digit classifications, 529 three-digit classifications, and 6,006 five-digit classifications..
- Web site: MSC2020-Mathematics Subject Classification System . zbMath . Associate Editors of Mathematical Reviews and zbMATH . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20240102023805/https://zbmath.org/static/msc2020.pdf . January 2, 2024 . February 3, 2024.
- Book: LeVeque, William J. . William J. LeVeque . 1977 . Introduction . Fundamentals of Number Theory . 1–30 . . 0-201-04287-8 . 76055645 . 3519779 . 118560854.
- Book: Goldman, Jay R. . 1998 . The Founding Fathers . The Queen of Mathematics: A Historically Motivated Guide to Number Theory . 2–3 . A K Peters . Wellesley, MA . 10.1201/9781439864623 . 1-56881-006-7 . 94020017 . 30437959 . 118934517.
- Book: Weil, André . André Weil . 1983 . Number Theory: An Approach Through History From Hammurapi to Legendre . Birkhäuser Boston . 2–3 . 10.1007/978-0-8176-4571-7 . 0-8176-3141-0 . 83011857 . 9576587 . 117789303.
- Kleiner . Israel . Israel Kleiner (mathematician) . March 2000 . From Fermat to Wiles: Fermat's Last Theorem Becomes a Theorem . Elemente der Mathematik . 55 . 1 . 19–37 . 10.1007/PL00000079 . free . 0013-6018 . 1420-8962 . 66083524 . 1567783 . 53319514.
- Book: Wang, Yuan . 2002 . The Goldbach Conjecture . 1–18 . 2nd . Series in Pure Mathematics . 4 . . 10.1142/5096 . 981-238-159-7 . 2003268597 . 51533750 . 14555830.
- Straume . Eldar . September 4, 2014 . A Survey of the Development of Geometry up to 1870 . math.HO . 1409.1140 .
- Book: Hilbert, David . David Hilbert . 1902 . [{{GBurl|id=8ZBsAAAAMAAJ}} The Foundations of Geometry ]. 1 . . 10.1126/science.16.399.307 . 02019303 . 996838 . 238499430 . February 6, 2024.
- Book: Hartshorne, Robin . Robin Hartshorne . 2000 . Euclid's Geometry . 9–13 . [{{GBurl|id=EJCSL9S6la0C|p=9}} Geometry: Euclid and Beyond ]. . 0-387-98650-2 . 99044789 . 42290188 . February 7, 2024.
- Book: Boyer, Carl B. . Carl B. Boyer . 2004 . 1956 . Fermat and Descartes . 74–102 . History of Analytic Geometry . . 0-486-43832-5 . 2004056235 . 56317813.
- Stump . 1997 . David J. . Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900 . . 5 . 3 . 383–417 . 10.1162/posc_a_00532 . 1530-9274 . 1063-6145 . 94657506 . 26085129 . 117709681 . February 8, 2024.
- Web site: O'Connor . J. J. . Robertson . E. F. . February 1996 . Non-Euclidean geometry . MacTuror . . Scotland, UK . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221106142807/https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/HistTopics/Non-Euclidean_geometry/ . November 6, 2022 . February 8, 2024.
- Christianidis . Jean . Oaks . Jeffrey . May 2013 . Practicing algebra in late antiquity: The problem-solving of Diophantus of Alexandria . Historia Mathematica . 40 . 2 . 127–163 . 10.1016/j.hm.2012.09.001 . free . 1090-249X . 0315-0860 . 75642280 . 2240703 . 121346342.
- Web site: Shane . David . 2022 . Figurate Numbers: A Historical Survey of an Ancient Mathematics . . 20 . June 13, 2024 . In his work, Diophantus focused on deducing the arithmetic properties of figurate numbers, such as deducing the number of sides, the different ways a number can be expressed as a figurate number, and the formulation of the arithmetic progressions..
- Web site: Al-Khwarizmi . Overbay . Shawn . Schorer . Jimmy . Conger . Heather . . June 13, 2024.
- Web site: Lim . Lisa . December 21, 2018 . Where the x we use in algebra came from, and the X in Xmas . limited . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20181222003908/https://www.scmp.com/magazines/post-magazine/short-reads/article/2178856/where-x-we-use-algebra-came-and-x-xmas . December 22, 2018 . February 8, 2024 . South China Morning Post.
- Encyclopedia: Algebra . Berntjes . Sonja . Sonja Brentjes . . 3rd . en . 1573-3912 . 2007238847 . 56713464 . June 13, 2024.
- Oaks . Jeffery A. . 2018 . François Viète's revolution in algebra . . 72 . 3 . 245–302 . 10.1007/s00407-018-0208-0 . 1432-0657 . 0003-9519 . 63024699 . 1482042 . 125704699 . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221108162134/https://researchoutreach.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/02/Jeffrey-Oaks.pdf . November 8, 2022 . February 8, 2024.
- Web site: Variable in Maths . GeeksforGeeks . April 24, 2024 . June 13, 2024.
- Book: Corry, Leo . Leo Corry . 2004 . Emmy Noether: Ideals and Structures . [{{GBurl|id=WdGbeyehoCoC|p=247}} Modern Algebra and the Rise of Mathematical Structures ]. 247–252 . 2nd revised . Birkhäuser Basel . Germany . 3-7643-7002-5 . 2004556211 . 51234417 . February 8, 2024.
- Book: Riche, Jacques . Beziau . J. Y. . Costa-Leite . Alexandre . 2007 . From Universal Algebra to Universal Logic . 3–39 . [{{GBurl|id=ZoRN9T1GUVwC|p=3}} Perspectives on Universal Logic ]. Polimetrica International Scientific Publisher . Milano, Italy . 978-88-7699-077-9 . 647049731 . February 8, 2024.
- Book: Krömer, Ralph . 2007 . [{{GBurl|id=41bHxtHxjUAC|pg=PR20}} Tool and Object: A History and Philosophy of Category Theory ]. xxi–xxv, 1–91 . Science Networks – Historical Studies . 32 . . Germany . 978-3-7643-7523-2 . 2007920230 . 85242858 . February 8, 2024.
- Book: Guicciardini, Niccolo . Niccolò Guicciardini . Schliesser . Eric . Smeenk . Chris . 2017 . The Newton–Leibniz Calculus Controversy, 1708–1730 . The Oxford Handbook of Newton . Oxford Handbooks . . 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199930418.013.9 . 978-0-19-993041-8 . 975829354 . https://core.ac.uk/download/pdf/187993169.pdf . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221109163253/https://core.ac.uk/download/pdf/187993169.pdf . November 9, 2022 . February 9, 2024.
- Web site: O'Connor . J. J. . Robertson . E. F. . September 1998 . Leonhard Euler . MacTutor . . Scotland, UK . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221109164921/https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/Euler/ . November 9, 2022 . February 9, 2024.
- Web site: Calculus (Differential and Integral Calculus with Examples) . . June 13, 2024.
- Franklin . James . James Franklin (philosopher) . July 2017 . Discrete and Continuous: A Fundamental Dichotomy in Mathematics . Journal of Humanistic Mathematics . 7 . 2 . 355–378 . 10.5642/jhummath.201702.18 . free . 2159-8118 . 2011202231 . 700943261 . 6945363 . February 9, 2024.
- Book: Maurer, Stephen B. . Rosenstein . Joseph G. . Franzblau . Deborah S. . Roberts . Fred S. . Fred S. Roberts . 1997 . What is Discrete Mathematics? The Many Answers . 121–124 . Discrete Mathematics in the Schools . DIMACS: Series in Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical Computer Science . 36 . . 10.1090/dimacs/036/13 . 0-8218-0448-0 . 1052-1798 . 97023277 . 37141146 . 67358543 . . February 9, 2024.
- Book: Hales, Thomas C. . Turing's Legacy . Thomas Callister Hales . Downey . Rod . Rod Downey . 2014 . 260–261 . Turing's Legacy: Developments from Turing's Ideas in Logic . . Lecture Notes in Logic . 42 . 10.1017/CBO9781107338579.001 . 978-1-107-04348-0 . 2014000240 . 867717052 . 19315498 . . February 9, 2024.
- Sipser . Michael . Michael Sipser . July 1992 . The History and Status of the P versus NP Question . STOC '92: Proceedings of the twenty-fourth annual ACM symposium on Theory of Computing . 603–618 . 10.1145/129712.129771 . 11678884.
- Encyclopedia: The Emergence of First-Order Logic . Ewald . William . November 17, 2018 . . 1095-5054 . sn97004494 . 37550526 . June 14, 2024.
- Encyclopedia: The Early Development of Set Theory . Ferreirós . José . June 18, 2020 . First published April 10, 2007 . . 1095-5054 . sn97004494 . 37550526 . June 14, 2024.
- Ferreirós . José . December 2001 . The Road to Modern Logic—An Interpretation . The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic . 7 . 4 . 441–484 . 10.2307/2687794 . 2687794 . 1079-8986 . 1943-5894 . 11441/38373 . 95652899 . 31616719 . 43258676 . June 14, 2024.
- Web site: Dispute over Infinity Divides Mathematicians . Wolchover . Natalie . Natalie Wolchover . November 26, 2013 . . June 14, 2024.
- Web site: Wittgenstein's analysis on Cantor's diagonal argument . Zhuang . Chaohui . DOC . . June 14, 2024.
- Book: Tanswell, Fenner Stanley . Mathematical Rigour and Informal Proof . Cambridge Elements in the Philosophy of Mathematics . 2024 . . 10.1017/9781009325110 . 978-1-00-949438-0 . 2514-3808 . 2399-2883 . 1418750041.
- Web site: Avigad . Jeremy . Jeremy Avigad . Reck . Erich H. . December 11, 2001 . "Clarifying the nature of the infinite": the development of metamathematics and proof theory . . June 14, 2024.
- Book: Hamilton
, Alan G.
. [{{GBurl|id=OXfmTHXvRXMC|p=3}}
Numbers, Sets and Axioms: The Apparatus of Mathematics
]. 3–4 . 1982 . 978-0-521-28761-6 . Cambridge University Press . November 12, 2022.
- 10.2307/2689412 . The Three Crises in Mathematics: Logicism, Intuitionism, and Formalism . Mathematics Magazine . September 1979 . Ernst . Snapper . Ernst Snapper . 52 . 4 . 207–216 . 2689412 . 0025-570X .
- On the Philosophical Relevance of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems . Panu . Raatikainen . Revue Internationale de Philosophie . 59 . 4 . October 2005 . 513–534 . 10.3917/rip.234.0513 . 23955909 . 52083793 . November 12, 2022 . November 12, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221112212555/https://www.cairn.info/revue-internationale-de-philosophie-2005-4-page-513.htm . live .
- Web site: Intuitionistic Logic . September 4, 2018. Joan . Moschovakis . Joan Moschovakis . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . November 12, 2022. December 16, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221216154821/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-intuitionistic/ . live .
- At the Heart of Analysis: Intuitionism and Philosophy . Charles . McCarty . Philosophia Scientiæ, Cahier spécial 6 . 2006 . 81–94 . 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.411. free.
- Web site: Halpern . Joseph . Joseph Halpern . Harper . Robert . Robert Harper (computer scientist) . Immerman . Neil . Neil Immerman . Kolaitis . Phokion . Phokion Kolaitis . Vardi . Moshe . Moshe Vardi . Vianu . Victor . Victor Vianu . On the Unusual Effectiveness of Logic in Computer Science . January 15, 2021 . 2001 . March 3, 2021. https://web.archive.org/web/20210303115643/https://www.cs.cmu.edu/~rwh/papers/unreasonable/basl.pdf . live .
- Book: Rao, C. Radhakrishna . C. R. Rao . 1997 . 1989 . Statistics and Truth: Putting Chance to Work . 2nd . 3–17, 63–70 . World Scientific . 981-02-3111-3 . 97010349 . 1474730 . 36597731.
- Book: Rao, C. Radhakrishna . C.R. Rao . Arthanari . T.S. . Dodge . Yadolah . Yadolah Dodge . Foreword . Mathematical programming in statistics . Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics . Wiley . New York . 1981 . vii–viii . 978-0-471-08073-2 . 80021637 . 607328 . 6707805.
- Web site: G I Marchuk's plenary: ICM 1970 . Gurii Ivanovich . Marchuk . MacTutor . April 2020 . School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland . November 13, 2022. November 13, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221113155409/https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Extras/Computational_mathematics/ . live .
- [{{GBurl|id=jYNIDwAAQBAJ|p=28}} Grand Challenges, High Performance Computing, and Computational Science ]. Johnson . Gary M. . Cavallini . John S. . Singapore Supercomputing Conference'90: Supercomputing For Strategic Advantage . September 1991 . 28 . 91018998 . World Scientific . Kang Hoh . Phua . Kia Fock . Loe . November 13, 2022 .
- Book: Trefethen, Lloyd N. . Lloyd N. Trefethen . Gowers . Timothy . Timothy Gowers . Barrow-Green . June . June Barrow-Green . Leader . Imre . Imre Leader . 2008 . Numerical Analysis . 604–615 . The Princeton Companion to Mathematics . . 978-0-691-11880-2 . 2008020450 . 2467561 . 227205932 . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20230307054158/http://people.maths.ox.ac.uk/trefethen/NAessay.pdf . March 7, 2023 . February 15, 2024.
- See, for example, Book: Wilder, Raymond L. . Raymond L. Wilder. Evolution of Mathematical Concepts; an Elementary Study. passim.
- Book: Zaslavsky, Claudia. Claudia Zaslavsky. Africa Counts: Number and Pattern in African Culture.. 1999. Chicago Review Press. 978-1-61374-115-3. 843204342.
- https://www.ms.uky.edu/~dhje223/CrestOfThePeacockCh4-pages-2-21.pdf/ Mesopotamia
- Book: Heath, Thomas Little . Thomas Heath (classicist) . A History of Greek Mathematics: From Thales to Euclid . registration . 1 . New York . Dover Publications . 1981 . 1921 . 978-0-486-24073-2.
- Mueller . I. . 1969 . Euclid's Elements and the Axiomatic Method . The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science . 20 . 4 . 289–309 . 10.1093/bjps/20.4.289 . 686258 . 0007-0882.
- Book: Ore
, Øystein
. [{{GBurl|id=Sl_6BPp7S0AC|pg=IA19}}
Number Theory and Its History
]. Øystein Ore . Courier Corporation . 19–24 . 1988 . 978-0-486-65620-5 . November 14, 2022.
- On the Use of Series in Hindu Mathematics . A. N. . Singh . Osiris . 1 . January 1936 . 606–628 . 10.1086/368443 . 301627. 144760421 .
- Book: Use of series in India . Kolachana . A. . Mahesh . K. . Ramasubramanian . K. . Studies in Indian Mathematics and Astronomy . Sources and Studies in the History of Mathematics and Physical Sciences . 438–461 . Springer . Singapore . 978-981-13-7325-1 . 2019 . 10.1007/978-981-13-7326-8_20 . 190176726 .
- Book: Saliba, George . George Saliba . A history of Arabic astronomy: planetary theories during the golden age of Islam . 1994 . New York University Press . 978-0-8147-7962-0 . 28723059 .
- Contributions of Islamic scholars to the scientific enterprise . Yasmeen M. . Faruqi . International Education Journal . 2006 . 7 . 4 . 391–399 . Shannon Research Press . November 14, 2022. November 14, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221114165547/https://eric.ed.gov/?id=EJ854295 . live .
- Greek-Arabic-Latin: The Transmission of Mathematical Texts in the Middle Ages . Richard . Lorch . Science in Context . 14 . 1–2 . June 2001 . 313–331 . Cambridge University Press . 10.1017/S0269889701000114 . 146539132 . December 5, 2022 . December 17, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221217160922/https://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/15929/1/greek-arabic-latin.pdf . live .
- Book: Kent, Benjamin . History of Science . Bibliotex Digital Library . 2022 . 978-1-984668-67-7 . 2 .
- History of Mathematics After the Sixteenth Century . Raymond Clare . Archibald . Raymond Clare Archibald . The American Mathematical Monthly . Part 2: Outline of the History of Mathematics . 56 . 1 . January 1949 . 35–56 . 10.2307/2304570 . 2304570.
- Wolfram . Stephan . October 2000 . Stephen Wolfram . Mathematical Notation: Past and Future . MathML and Math on the Web: MathML International Conference 2000, Urbana Champaign, USA . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221116150905/https://www.stephenwolfram.com/publications/mathematical-notation-past-future/ . November 16, 2022 . February 3, 2024.
- Douglas . Heather . Headley . Marcia Gail . Hadden . Stephanie . LeFevre . Jo-Anne . Jo-Anne LeFevre . December 3, 2020 . Knowledge of Mathematical Symbols Goes Beyond Numbers . Journal of Numerical Cognition . 6 . 3 . 322–354 . 10.5964/jnc.v6i3.293 . free . 2363-8761 . 228085700.
- Web site: Letourneau . Mary . Wright Sharp . Jennifer . October 2017 . AMS Style Guide . 75 . . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221208063650/https://www.ams.org//publications/authors/AMS-StyleGuide-online.pdf . December 8, 2022 . February 3, 2024.
- Jansen . Anthony R. . Marriott . Kim . Yelland . Greg W. . 2000 . Constituent Structure in Mathematical Expressions . Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society . 22 . . 1069-7977 . 68713073 . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20221116152222/https://escholarship.org/content/qt35r988q9/qt35r988q9.pdf . November 16, 2022 . February 3, 2024.
- Book: Rossi, Richard J. . 2006 . Theorems, Corollaries, Lemmas, and Methods of Proof . Pure and Applied Mathematics: A Wiley Series of Texts, Monographs and Tracts . . 1–14, 47–48 . 978-0-470-04295-3 . 2006041609 . 64085024.
- Web site: Earliest Uses of Some Words of Mathematics . MacTutor . . Scotland, UK . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20220929032236/https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Miller/mathword/ . September 29, 2022 . February 3, 2024.
- Silver . Daniel S. . November–December 2017 . The New Language of Mathematics . The American Scientist . 105 . 6 . 364–371 . . 10.1511/2017.105.6.364 . free . 0003-0996 . 43020253 . 1480717 . 125455764.
- Book: [{{GBurl|id=pJAvWaRYo3UC}} Modelling Mathematical Methods and Scientific Computation ]. Nicola . Bellomo . Luigi . Preziosi . CRC Press . December 22, 1994 . 1 . 978-0-8493-8331-1 . Mathematical Modeling . 1 . November 16, 2022 .
- Mathematical Models and Reality: A Constructivist Perspective . Christian . Hennig . Foundations of Science . 15 . 29–48 . 2010 . 10.1007/s10699-009-9167-x . 6229200 . November 17, 2022.
- Models in Science . February 4, 2020 . Roman . Frigg . Roman Frigg . Stephan . Hartmann . Stephan Hartmann . Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . November 17, 2022 . November 17, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221117162412/https://seop.illc.uva.nl/entries/models-science/ . live .
- Book: Stewart, Ian . Ian Stewart (mathematician) . Mathematics, Maps, and Models . The Map and the Territory: Exploring the Foundations of Science, Thought and Reality . 345–356 . Springer . 2018 . Shyam . Wuppuluri . Francisco Antonio . Doria . 978-3-319-72478-2 . The Frontiers Collection . . 10.1007/978-3-319-72478-2_18 . November 17, 2022 .
- Web site: The science checklist applied: Mathematics. Understanding Science . University of California, Berkeley . October 27, 2019. https://web.archive.org/web/20191027021023/https://undsci.berkeley.edu/article/mathematics. October 27, 2019. live.
- Book: Mackay, A. L. . 1991 . [{{GBurl|id=KwESE88CGa8C|q=durch planmässiges Tattonieren}} Dictionary of Scientific Quotations ]. London . 100 . 978-0-7503-0106-0 . Taylor & Francis . March 19, 2023 .
- Book: Bishop . Alan . 1991 . Environmental activities and mathematical culture . Mathematical Enculturation: A Cultural Perspective on Mathematics Education . . 20–59 . Norwell, Massachusetts . Kluwer Academic Publishers . 978-0-7923-1270-3 . April 5, 2020 .
- Book: Out of Their Minds: The Lives and Discoveries of 15 Great Computer Scientists . Shasha . Dennis Elliot . Dennis Elliot Shasha . Lazere . Cathy A. . Springer . 1998 . 228 . 978-0-387-98269-4 .
- Book: Nickles, Thomas . 2013 . The Problem of Demarcation . Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem . 104 . Chicago . The University of Chicago Press . 978-0-226-05182-6 .
- 2014. Pigliucci. Massimo . Massimo Pigliucci . Are There 'Other' Ways of Knowing? . Philosophy Now. April 6, 2020. May 13, 2020 . https://web.archive.org/web/20200513190522/https://philosophynow.org/issues/102/Are_There_Other_Ways_of_Knowing . live.
- Book: Ferreirós, J.
. The Shaping of Arithmetic after C.F. Gauss's Disquisitiones Arithmeticae . Ό Θεὸς Άριθμητίζει: The Rise of Pure Mathematics as Arithmetic with Gauss . 235–268 . 2007 . 978-3-540-34720-0 . Catherine . Goldstein . Catherine Goldstein . Norbert . Schappacher . Joachim . Schwermer . Springer Science & Business Media . .
- Mathematical vs. Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science . Thomas S. . Kuhn . Thomas Kuhn . The Journal of Interdisciplinary History . 1976 . 7 . 1 . 1–31 . The MIT Press . 202372 . 10.2307/202372.
- Book: Asper
, Markus
. The two cultures of mathematics in ancient Greece . 2009 . The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics . Eleanor . Robson . Jacqueline . Stedall . 107–132 . 978-0-19-921312-2 . OUP Oxford . Oxford Handbooks in Mathematics . . November 18, 2022.
- Book: Gozwami . Pinkimani . Singh . Madan Mohan . Ahmad . Khaleel . Doja . M. N. . Udzir . Nur Izura . Singh . Manu Pratap . 2019 . 59–60 . Integer Factorization Problem . Emerging Security Algorithms and Techniques . CRC Press . 978-0-8153-6145-9 . 2019010556 . 1082226900.
- How applied mathematics became pure . Maddy . P. . Penelope Maddy . The Review of Symbolic Logic . 2008 . 1 . 1 . 16–41 . 10.1017/S1755020308080027 . 18122406 . November 19, 2022. August 12, 2017. https://web.archive.org/web/20170812012210/http://pgrim.org/philosophersannual/pa28articles/maddyhowapplied.pdf . live .
- Book: Silver
, Daniel S.
. The Best Writing on Mathematics, 2016 . In Defense of Pure Mathematics . 17–26 . 978-0-691-17529-4 . 2017 . Mircea . Pitici . Princeton University Press . . November 19, 2022.
- The American Mathematical Society and Applied Mathematics from the 1920s to the 1950s: A Revisionist Account . Karen Hunger . Parshall . Karen Hunger Parshall . Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society . 59 . 2022 . 3 . 405–427 . 10.1090/bull/1754 . 249561106 . November 20, 2022 . free . November 20, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221120151259/https://www.ams.org/journals/bull/2022-59-03/S0273-0979-2022-01754-5/home.html . live .
- The History Of Applied Mathematics And The History Of Society . Michael . Stolz . Synthese . 133 . 43–57 . 2002 . 10.1023/A:1020823608217 . 34271623 . November 20, 2022.
- On the role of applied mathematics . . C. C . . Lin . 19 . 3 . March 1976 . 267–288 . 10.1016/0001-8708(76)90024-4 . free.
- Applying Pure Mathematics . Anthony . Peressini . Philosophy of Science. Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers . 66 . September 1999 . S1–S13 . 188757 . November 30, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20240102210931/https://d1wqtxts1xzle7.cloudfront.net/32799272/ApplyingMathPSA-libre.pdf?1391205742=&response-content-disposition=inline%3B+filename%3DApplying_Pure_Mathematics.pdf&Expires=1704233371&Signature=BvNJyYufdj9BiKFe94w6gdXLpAfr7T5JIv~RU74R2uT0O9Ngj6i4cdBtYYOSB6D4V-MgButb6lKNhIGGQogw0e0sHVFkJUy5TRsoCiQ-MLabpZOf74E5SGLMFIExhGVAw7SKrSFaQsFGhfbaRMxbMP~u-wRdJAz6ve6kbWr6oq-doQeEOlRfO4EByNCUYx-KAk3~cBsH1Q2WNZ5QiVObMI1ufQ7zkQM1bqzOumLu6g07F~pt~Cds~lftuQufHomoTH-V9H9iKQgUyc3-4bEB1y1Jdngs7WWg76LcSGn65bPK8dxvsZzKaLDGfoK5jamZkA8z3-xxiMIPL8c6YETjZA__&Key-Pair-Id=APKAJLOHF5GGSLRBV4ZA . January 2, 2024. live .
- Mathematics meets physics: A contribution to their interaction in the 19th and the first half of the 20th century . Lützen . J. . 2011 . Schlote . K. H. . Schneider . M. . Verlag Harri Deutsch . Frankfurt am Main . Examples and reflections on the interplay between mathematics and physics in the 19th and 20th century . https://slub.qucosa.de/api/qucosa%3A16267/zip/ . November 19, 2022. March 23, 2023. https://web.archive.org/web/20230323164143/https://slub.qucosa.de/api/qucosa%3A16267/zip/ . live .
- Model theory and exponentiation . Marker . Dave . Notices of the American Mathematical Society . 43 . 7 . July 1996 . 753–759 . November 19, 2022. March 13, 2014. https://web.archive.org/web/20140313004011/http://www.ams.org/notices/199607/ . live .
- Cylindrical Algebraic Decomposition in the RegularChains Library . Changbo . Chen . Marc Moreno . Maza . August 2014 . 8592 . Springer . Berlin . International Congress on Mathematical Software 2014 . Lecture Notes in Computer Science . November 19, 2022 . 10.1007/978-3-662-44199-2_65 .
- Purifying applied mathematics and applying pure mathematics: how a late Wittgensteinian perspective sheds light onto the dichotomy . José Antonio . Pérez-Escobar . Deniz . Sarikaya . European Journal for Philosophy of Science . 12 . 1 . 1–22 . 2021 . 10.1007/s13194-021-00435-9 . 245465895. free .
- Book: Takase
, M.
. Pure Mathematics and Applied Mathematics are Inseparably Intertwined: Observation of the Early Analysis of the Infinity . A Mathematical Approach to Research Problems of Science and Technology . Mathematics for Industry . 5 . 2014 . 393–399 . Springer . Tokyo . . 10.1007/978-4-431-55060-0_29 . 978-4-431-55059-4 . November 20, 2022.
- The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences . Wigner . Eugene . Eugene Wigner . . 13 . 1 . 1–14 . 1960 . 10.1002/cpa.3160130102 . 1960CPAM...13....1W . 6112252 . live . https://web.archive.org/web/20110228152633/http://www.dartmouth.edu/~matc/MathDrama/reading/Wigner.html . February 28, 2011 . mdy-all.
- Revisiting the 'unreasonable effectiveness' of mathematics . Sundar . Sarukkai . Current Science . 88 . 3 . February 10, 2005 . 415–423 . 24110208.
- Book: Wagstaff
, Samuel S. Jr.
. History of Integer Factoring . 41–77 . Computational Cryptography, Algorithmic Aspects of Cryptography, A Tribute to AKL . Joppe W. . Bos . Martijn . Stam . London Mathematical Society Lecture Notes Series 469 . Cambridge University Press . 2021 . https://www.cs.purdue.edu/homes/ssw/chapter3.pdf . November 20, 2022. November 20, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221120155733/https://www.cs.purdue.edu/homes/ssw/chapter3.pdf . live .
- Web site: Curves: Ellipse . MacTutor . School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland . November 20, 2022. October 14, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221014051943/https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Curves/Ellipse/ . live .
- Web site: Beyond the Surface of Einstein's Relativity Lay a Chimerical Geometry . Vasudevan . Mukunth . The Wire . September 10, 2015. November 20, 2022. November 20, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221120191206/https://thewire.in/science/beyond-the-surface-of-einsteins-relativity-lay-a-chimerical-geometry . live .
- The Space-Time Manifold of Relativity. The Non-Euclidean Geometry of Mechanics and Electromagnetics . Edwin B. . Wilson . Gilbert N. . Lewis . Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences . 48 . 11 . November 1912 . 389–507 . 10.2307/20022840 . 20022840 .
- Discovering the Positron (I) . Norwood Russell . Hanson . Norwood Russell Hanson . The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science . 12 . 47 . November 1961 . 194–214 . The University of Chicago Press . 685207 . 10.1093/bjps/xiii.49.54.
- Avoiding reification: Heuristic effectiveness of mathematics and the prediction of the Ω– particle . Michele . Ginammi . Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics . 53 . February 2016 . 20–27 . 10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.12.001. 2016SHPMP..53...20G .
- Book: Wagh . Sanjay Moreshwar . [{{GBurl|id=-DmfVjBUPksC|p=3}} Essentials of Physics ]. Deshpande . Dilip Abasaheb . September 27, 2012 . PHI Learning Pvt. Ltd. . 978-81-203-4642-0 . 3 . en . January 3, 2023 .
- Atiyah . Michael . Michael Atiyah . 1990 . On the Work of Edward Witten . Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians . 31 . https://web.archive.org/web/20130928095313/http://www.mathunion.org/ICM/ICM1990.1/Main/icm1990.1.0031.0036.ocr.pdf . September 28, 2013 . December 29, 2022.
- Web site: Course 18C Mathematics with Computer Science . June 1, 2024 . math.mit.edu.
- Web site: Theoretical Computer Science . June 1, 2024 . math.mit.edu.
- Web site: April 8, 2024 . Real-Life Applications of Discrete Mathematics . May 19, 2024 . GeeksforGeeks . en-US.
- Hales . Thomas . Adams . Mark . Bauer . Gertrud . Dang . Tat Dat . Harrison . John . Hoang . Le Truong . Kaliszyk . Cezary . Magron . Victor . Mclaughlin . Sean . Nguyen . Tat Thang . Nguyen . Quang Truong . Nipkow . Tobias . Obua . Steven . Pleso . Joseph . Rute . Jason . Solovyev . Alexey . Ta . Thi Hoai An . Tran . Nam Trung . Trieu . Thi Diep . Urban . Josef . Vu . Ky . Zumkeller . Roland . A Formal Proof of the Kepler Conjecture . Forum of Mathematics, Pi . 2017 . 5 . e2 . 10.1017/fmp.2017.1 . 216912822 . en . 2050-5086 . February 25, 2023 . December 4, 2020 . https://web.archive.org/web/20201204053232/https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/forum-of-mathematics-pi/article/formal-proof-of-the-kepler-conjecture/78FBD5E1A3D1BCCB8E0D5B0C463C9FBC . live . 2066/176365 . free .
- Book: Millstein, Roberta . Roberta Millstein . The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy . September 8, 2016 . Hájek . Alan . 601–622 . Probability in Biology: The Case of Fitness . 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199607617.013.27 . Hitchcock . Christopher . http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/10901/1/Millstein-fitness-v2.pdf . December 29, 2022 . March 7, 2023 . https://web.archive.org/web/20230307054456/http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/10901/1/Millstein-fitness-v2.pdf . live .
- See for example Anne Laurent, Roland Gamet, Jérôme Pantel, Tendances nouvelles en modélisation pour l'environnement, actes du congrès «Programme environnement, vie et sociétés» 15–17 janvier 1996, CNRS
- Web site: January 5, 2022 . 1.4: The Lotka-Volterra Predator-Prey Model . December 29, 2022 . Mathematics LibreTexts . en . December 29, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221229204111/https://math.libretexts.org/Bookshelves/Applied_Mathematics/Mathematical_Biology_(Chasnov)/01:_Population_Dynamics/1.04:_The_Lotka-Volterra_Predator-Prey_Model . live .
- Salsburg . David . August 17, 1992 . Commentary . The Use of Statistical Methods in the Analysis of Clinical Studies . 46 . 17.
- Book: Beyond the Molecular Frontier: Challenges for Chemistry and Chemical Engineering . NAP.edu . 2003 . 978-0-309-16839-7 . 71–73 . en . 8 . 10.17226/10633. 25032300 . National Research Council . National Research Council (United States) .
- Web site: Catastrophe Models (Property) . May 19, 2024 . content.naic.org . en.
- Web site: MAM2001 Essay . May 19, 2024 . ww2.amstat.org.
- Web site: Hill . Mullica . September 7, 2022 . HOW MATH IS USED IN WEATHER FORECASTING . May 19, 2024 . www.mathnasium.com.
- Web site: Using Mathematical Models to Investigate Planetary Habitability . May 19, 2024 . NASA.
- Edling . Christofer R. . 2002 . Mathematics in Sociology . Annual Review of Sociology . en . 28 . 1 . 197–220 . 10.1146/annurev.soc.28.110601.140942 . 0360-0572.
- Book: Zak, Paul J. . [{{GBurl|id=6QrvmNo2qD4C|p=158}} Moral Markets: The Critical Role of Values in the Economy ]. 2010 . 158 . Princeton University Press . 978-1-4008-3736-6 . en . January 3, 2023 .
- Book: Introduction to Choice Theory . Jonathan . Levin . Paul . Milgrom . September 2004.
- Book: Kremer, Michael . Rao, Gautam . Schilbach, Frank . Handbook of Behavioral Economics: Applications and Foundations . Chapter 5 Behavioral development economics . 2019 . 2.
- Web site: Mathematics. www.mdpi.com.
- Web site: Kondratiev, Nikolai Dmitrievich Encyclopedia.com . December 29, 2022 . www.encyclopedia.com . July 1, 2016 . https://web.archive.org/web/20160701224009/http://www.encyclopedia.com/doc/1G2-3404100667.html . live .
- Web site: Mathématique de l'histoire-géometrie et cinématique. Lois de Brück. Chronologie géodésique de la Bible., by Charles LAGRANGE et al. | The Online Books Page. onlinebooks.library.upenn.edu.
- Web site: Cliodynamics: a science for predicting the future . December 29, 2022 . ZDNET . en . December 29, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221229204104/https://www.zdnet.com/article/cliodynamics-a-science-for-predicting-the-future/ . live .
- Book: Sokal, Alan. Fashionable Nonsense. Jean Bricmont. Picador. 1998. 978-0-312-19545-8. New York. 39605994. Alan Sokal. Jean Bricmont.
- Web site: Biden's Misleading Unemployment Statistic – FactCheck.org.
- Web site: Modern Macroeconomic Models as Tools for Economic Policy | Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis. www.minneapolisfed.org.
- Book: Beaujouan, Guy . [{{GBurl|id=92n7ZE8Iww8C|p=130}} Comprendre et maîtriser la nature au Moyen Age: mélanges d'histoire des sciences offerts à Guy Beaujouan ]. 1994 . Librairie Droz . 978-2-600-00040-6 . 130 . fr . January 3, 2023 .
- Web site: L'astrologie à l'épreuve : ça ne marche pas, ça n'a jamais marché ! / Afis Science – Association française pour l'information scientifique . December 28, 2022 . Afis Science – Association française pour l’information scientifique . fr . January 29, 2023 . https://web.archive.org/web/20230129204349/https://www.afis.org/L-astrologie-a-l-epreuve-ca-ne-marche-pas-ca-n-a-jamais-marche . live .
- Encyclopedia: Platonism in Metaphysics . The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Balaguer . Mark . Zalta . Edward N. . 2016 . Spring 2016 . Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University . April 2, 2022 . January 30, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20220130174043/https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/platonism/ . live .
- Book: Dorato
, Mauro
. The Software of the Universe, An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Laws of Nature . 2005 . Why are laws mathematical? . 31–66 . 978-0-7546-3994-7 . Ashgate . https://www.academia.edu/download/52076815/2ch.pdf . December 5, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20230817111932/https://d1wqtxts1xzle7.cloudfront.net/52076815/2ch-libre.pdf?1488997736=&response-content-disposition=inline%3B+filename%3DChapter_2_of_the_book_the_software_of_th.pdf&Expires=1692274771&Signature=PXpNLBsmWMkz9YUs6~LUOfXNkmkCAmDfxQUoWOkGJKP4YqPGQUFMuP1I0xFycLZkL0dyfGwdGQ7mPk44nvmpM3YpKBSeVCZRXtDMiwgqs1JhEWrJovAhrchPLM1mGn3pw5P6LPo0sDZsl7uaPoZHMyCyJpayHvFtpyj1oUMIdmGuYM5P3euy1R87g6xlKyNAp~~BR5I4gVpopzLoeZn7d3oEnOOua0GjsqsZ6H9mEgcZMpH-qF8w9iFa9aSXFpqxagQwcVVkg7DXkOjVV5jyzctBUKQtOQQ~-9EN1y-c9pFV-Xu-NNuoN3Ij6K4SwvjYv0a8DMs8T5SVj1Kz9i4CEQ__&Key-Pair-Id=APKAJLOHF5GGSLRBV4ZA . August 17, 2023. live .
- Images of Mathematics Held by University Teachers of Mathematical Sciences . Mura . Roberta . Dec 1993 . Educational Studies in Mathematics . 25 . 4 . 375–85 . 10.1007/BF01273907 . 3482762 . 122351146.
- Book: [{{GBurl|id=EDm0eQqFUQ4C|p=9}}
Iris Runge: A Life at the Crossroads of Mathematics, Science, and Industry
]. Tobies . Renate . Renate Tobies . Helmut . Neunzert . Springer . 2012 . 978-3-0348-0229-1 . 9 . [I]t is first necessary to ask what is meant by mathematics in general. Illustrious scholars have debated this matter until they were blue in the face, and yet no consensus has been reached about whether mathematics is a natural science, a branch of the humanities, or an art form. . June 20, 2015.
- "What is Mathematics?" and why we should ask, where one should experience and learn that, and how to teach it . Günter M. . Ziegler . Günter M. Ziegler . Andreas . Loos . Kaiser . G. . Proceedings of the 13th International Congress on Mathematical Education . ICME-13 Monographs . November 2, 2017 . 63–77 . Springer . 10.1007/978-3-319-62597-3_5. 978-3-319-62596-6 .
- Book: Franklin, James . James Franklin (philosopher) . [{{GBurl|id=mbn35b2ghgkC|p=104}} Philosophy of Mathematics ]. 2009 . 978-0-08-093058-9 . 104–106 . Elsevier . June 20, 2015 .
- Book: Cajori
, Florian
. [{{GBurl|id=mGJRjIC9fZgC|p=285}}
A History of Mathematics
]. Florian Cajori . American Mathematical Society (1991 reprint) . 1893 . 978-0-8218-2102-2 . 285–286 . June 20, 2015.
- Book: Saunders Maclane. 1986. Mathematics, form and function. Springer., page 409
- The Methodology of Mathematics . Ronald . Brown . Ronald Brown (mathematician) . Timothy . Porter . The Mathematical Gazette . 79 . 485 . 321–334 . January 2000 . 10.2307/3618304 . 3618304 . 178923299 . November 25, 2022 . March 23, 2023 . https://web.archive.org/web/20230323164159/https://cds.cern.ch/record/280311 . live .
- Strauss . Danie . 2011 . Defining mathematics . Acta Academica . 43 . 4 . 1–28 . November 25, 2022.
- Mathematical Rigor and Proof . Yacin . Hamami . The Review of Symbolic Logic . 15 . 2 . June 2022 . 409–449 . November 21, 2022 . 10.1017/S1755020319000443 . 209980693 . December 5, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221205114343/https://www.yacinhamami.com/wp-content/uploads/2019/12/Hamami-2019-Mathematical-Rigor-and-Proof.pdf . live .
"A few complain that the computer program can't be verified properly." (in reference to the Haken–Apple proof of the Four Color Theorem)
- On the Reliability of Mathematical Proofs . V. Ya. . Perminov . Philosophy of Mathematics . 42 . 167 (4) . 1988 . 500–508 . Revue Internationale de Philosophie.
- Teachers' perceptions of the official curriculum: Problem solving and rigor . Jon D. . Davis . Amy Roth . McDuffie . Corey . Drake . Amanda L. . Seiwell . International Journal of Educational Research . 93 . 2019 . 91–100 . 10.1016/j.ijer.2018.10.002 . 149753721 .
- Book: Endsley
, Kezia
. [{{GBurl|id=1cEYEAAAQBAJ|p=3}}
Mathematicians and Statisticians: A Practical Career Guide
]. 2021 . Practical Career Guides . 978-1-5381-4517-3 . Rowman & Littlefield . 1–3 . November 29, 2022.
- Book: Robson, Eleanor . The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics . Eleanor Robson . 2009 . Mathematics education in an Old Babylonian scribal school . Eleanor . Robson . Jacqueline . Stedall . Jackie Stedall . OUP Oxford . 978-0-19-921312-2 . . November 24, 2022.
- Book: Mathematics Education in Antiquity . Alain . Bernard . Christine . Proust . Christine Proust . Micah . Ross . Handbook on the History of Mathematics Education . Karp . A. . Schubring . G. . 2014 . 27–53 . 978-1-4614-9154-5 . Springer . New York . 10.1007/978-1-4614-9155-2_3.
- The World's First Mathematics Textbook . Underwood . Dudley . Math Horizons . 9 . 4 . April 2002 . 8–11 . Taylor & Francis, Ltd. . 10.1080/10724117.2002.11975154 . 25678363. 126067145 .
- Indian pedagogy and problem solving in ancient Thamizhakam . Subramarian . F. . History and Pedagogy of Mathematics conference, July 16–20, 2012 . November 29, 2022. November 28, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221128082654/http://hpm2012.onpcs.com/Proceeding/OT2/T2-10.pdf . live .
- Book: Siu
, Man Keung . Official Curriculum in Mathematics in Ancient China: How did Candidates Study for the Examination? . Series on Mathematics Education . How Chinese Learn Mathematics . 157–185 . 2004 . 1 . 978-981-256-014-8 . 10.1142/9789812562241_0006 . November 26, 2022 .
- The History of Mathematical Education . The American Mathematical Monthly . 74 . 1 . 38–55 . Taylor & Francis, Ltd. . 10.2307/2314867 . 2314867 . Jones . Phillip S. . 1967 .
- Introduction: the history of mathematics teaching. Indicators for modernization processes in societies . Gert . Schubring . Fulvia . Furinghetti . Man Keung . Siu . ZDM Mathematics Education . 44 . 457–459 . August 2012 . 4 . 10.1007/s11858-012-0445-7. 145507519 . free .
- Book: Examining eTIMSS Country Differences Between eTIMSS Data and Bridge Data: A Look at Country-Level Mode of Administration Effects . TIMSS 2019 International Results in Mathematics and Science . Matthias . von Davier . Pierre . Foy . Michael O. . Martin . Ina V.S. . Mullis . . 978-1-889938-54-7 . 13.1 . en-US . 2020 . November 29, 2022 . November 29, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221129163908/https://files.eric.ed.gov/fulltext/ED610099.pdf . live .
- Social Cognitive Factors, Support, and Engagement: Early Adolescents' Math Interests as Precursors to Choice of Career . Heather T. . Rowan-Kenyon . Amy K. . Swan . Marie F. . Creager . The Career Development Quarterly . 60 . 1 . March 2012 . 2–15 . 10.1002/j.2161-0045.2012.00001.x . November 29, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20231122212933/https://d1wqtxts1xzle7.cloudfront.net/45974312/j.2161-0045.2012.00001.x20160526-3995-67kydl-libre.pdf?1464293840=&response-content-disposition=inline%3B+filename%3DSocial_Cognitive_Factors_Support_and_Eng.pdf&Expires=1700692172&Signature=cs9KfTPxoPh859wY~ExtJyAl9NpYb3X-2P4rDel1Z3z7DwehsHLRggoZtgi1pMsamxYobu9dVK4G7OsqfvNxcuwz3uKh1pnCMZQEz~ahVtPb4kvN-4dmwExJplzoxWu31o3SJOfuBt0GGE-0Hl8eLfPBg5agmtkjSwAWQwlqGrjp3YgYZGjbNxOEAM4t1l4qvoWXidWvSHHcEUNvlKYwCDvG0~QhGTmA6ldxmfS1ovf0adog-qqvjGxxJuSjtP6O8zCTwkPXYwi2e8giI0H6b5fNarHc-2q~-NRnVVtYKhvSBcwC22kNZoA7s8sp8ix9KIdM3uxiUIBRBRC-4aaVoQ__&Key-Pair-Id=APKAJLOHF5GGSLRBV4ZA . November 22, 2023. live .
- Spotlight on math anxiety . Silke . Luttenberger . Sigrid . Wimmer . Manuela . Paechter . Psychology Research and Behavior Management . 2018 . 11 . 311–322 . 10.2147/PRBM.S141421 . 30123014 . 6087017 . free .
- The Outlook of the Mathematicians' Creative Processes . Narges . Yaftian . Procedia – Social and Behavioral Sciences . 191 . June 2, 2015 . 2519–2525 . 10.1016/j.sbspro.2015.04.617. free.
- The Frontage of Creativity and Mathematical Creativity . Mehdi . Nadjafikhah . Narges . Yaftian . Procedia – Social and Behavioral Sciences . 90 . October 10, 2013 . 344–350 . 10.1016/j.sbspro.2013.07.101. free.
- A proof that Euler missed... Apéry's Proof of the irrationality of ζ(3) . A. . van der Poorten . . 1 . 4 . 1979 . 195–203 . 10.1007/BF03028234 . 121589323 . November 22, 2022. September 6, 2015. https://web.archive.org/web/20150906015716/http://pracownicy.uksw.edu.pl/mwolf/Poorten_MI_195_0.pdf . live .
- Book: Petkovi
, Miodrag
. [{{GBurl|id=AZlwAAAAQBAJ|pg=PR13}}
Famous Puzzles of Great Mathematicians
]. September 2, 2009. American Mathematical Society . xiii–xiv . 978-0-8218-4814-2 . November 25, 2022.
- Book: Hardy, G. H. . A Mathematician's Apology . G. H. Hardy . Cambridge University Press . 1940 . 978-0-521-42706-7 . November 22, 2022. See also A Mathematician's Apology.
- Reflections on Paul Erdős on His Birth Centenary, Part II . Noga . Alon . Dan . Goldston . András . Sárközy . József . Szabados . Gérald . Tenenbaum . Stephan Ramon . Garcia . Amy L. . Shoemaker . Notices of the American Mathematical Society . March 2015 . 62 . 3 . 226–247 . Krishnaswami . Alladi . Steven G. . Krantz . 10.1090/noti1223. free .
- See, for example Bertrand Russell's statement "Mathematics, rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty ..." in his Book: History of Western Philosophy . 1919 . 60 .
- Borel . Armand . Armand Borel . Mathematics: Art and Science . The Mathematical Intelligencer . 5 . 4 . 9–17 . 1983 . Springer . 1027-488X . 10.4171/news/103/8. free.
- Cazden . Norman . October 1959 . 10.1177/002242945900700205 . 2 . Journal of Research in Music Education . 3344215 . 197–220 . Musical intervals and simple number ratios . 7. 220636812 .
- Budden . F. J. . October 1967 . 10.2307/3613237 . 377 . The Mathematical Gazette . 3613237 . 204–215 . Cambridge University Press . Modern mathematics and music . 51. 126119711 .
- Enquist . Magnus . Arak . Anthony . November 1994 . Symmetry, beauty and evolution . Nature . en . 372 . 6502 . 169–172 . 10.1038/372169a0 . 7969448 . 1994Natur.372..169E . 4310147 . 1476-4687 . December 29, 2022 . December 28, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20221228052049/https://www.nature.com/articles/372169a0 . live .
- Web site: Hestenes . David . 1999 . Symmetry Groups .
- Encyclopedia: Bender . Sara . Carducci . Bernardo J. . Nave . Christopher S. . Mio . Jeffrey S. . Riggio . Ronald E. . The Rorschach Test . September 2020 . 10.1002/9781119547167.ch131 . 367–376 . Wiley . The Wiley Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences: Measurement and Assessment. 978-1-119-05751-2 .
- Book: Weyl, Hermann. Symmetry. 47. Princeton Science Library. Hermann Weyl. Princeton University Press. 2015. 978-1-4008-7434-7. 4.
- Web site: Lecture 8: Translation Symmetry | Physics III: Vibrations and Waves | Physics. MIT OpenCourseWare.
- Web site: Bradley . Larry . 2010 . Fractals – Chaos & Fractals . December 29, 2022 . www.stsci.edu . March 7, 2023 . https://web.archive.org/web/20230307054609/https://www.stsci.edu/~lbradley/seminar/fractals.html . live .
- Web site: Self-similarity . December 29, 2022 . math.bu.edu . March 2, 2023 . https://web.archive.org/web/20230302132911/http://math.bu.edu/DYSYS/chaos-game/node5.html . live .
- Kissane . Barry . July 2009 . Popular mathematics . 22nd Biennial Conference of The Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers . Fremantle, Western Australia . Australian Association of Mathematics Teachers . 125–126 . December 29, 2022 . March 7, 2023 . https://web.archive.org/web/20230307054610/https://researchrepository.murdoch.edu.au/id/eprint/6242/ . live .
- Book: Steen, L. A. . [{{GBurl|id=-d3TBwAAQBAJ|dq="popular mathematics" analogies|p=2}} Mathematics Today Twelve Informal Essays ]. 2012. Springer Science & Business Media . 978-1-4613-9435-8 . 2 . en . January 3, 2023 .
- Book: Pitici, Mircea . [{{GBurl|id=9nGQDQAAQBAJ|dq="popular mathematics" analogies|p=331}} The Best Writing on Mathematics 2016 ]. 2017. Princeton University Press . 978-1-4008-8560-2 . en . January 3, 2023 .
- Web site: Fields Medal International Mathematical Union (IMU) . February 21, 2022 . www.mathunion.org . December 26, 2018 . https://web.archive.org/web/20181226015744/https://www.mathunion.org/imu-awards/fields-medal . live .
- Web site: Fields Medal . February 21, 2022 . Maths History . en . March 22, 2019 . https://web.archive.org/web/20190322134417/http://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Honours/FieldsMedal.html . live .
- Web site: Honours/Prizes Index . MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive . February 20, 2023. December 17, 2021. https://web.archive.org/web/20211217235828/https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Honours/ . live .
- Web site: About the Abel Prize. The Abel Prize. January 23, 2022. April 14, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20220414060442/https://abelprize.no/page/about-abel-prize. live.
- Encyclopedia: Abel Prize mathematics award. Encyclopedia Britannica. January 23, 2022. en. January 26, 2020. https://web.archive.org/web/20200126120202/https://www.britannica.com/science/Abel-Prize. live.
- Web site: June 1, 2009 . Chern Medal Award. live . https://web.archive.org/web/20090617012953/https://www.mathunion.org/fileadmin/IMU/Prizes/Chern/Chern_MedalPress_Release_090601.pdf . June 17, 2009 . February 21, 2022 . www.mathunion.org.
- Web site: Chern Medal Award. International Mathematical Union (IMU). January 23, 2022. August 25, 2010 . https://web.archive.org/web/20100825071850/http://www.mathunion.org/general/prizes/chern/details . live .
- Web site: The Leroy P Steele Prize of the AMS . School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews, Scotland . November 17, 2022. November 17, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20221117201134/https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Honours/AMSSteelePrize/ . live .
- Book: Chern . S. S. . Hirzebruch . F. . September 2000 . Wolf Prize in Mathematics . en . 10.1142/4149 . 978-981-02-3945-9 . February 21, 2022 . February 21, 2022 . https://web.archive.org/web/20220221171351/https://www.worldscientific.com/worldscibooks/10.1142/4149 . live .
- Web site: The Wolf Prize. live. https://web.archive.org/web/20200112205029/https://wolffund.org.il/the-wolf-prize/. January 12, 2020. January 23, 2022. Wolf Foundation. en-US.
- Web site: May 6, 2020. Hilbert's Problems: 23 and Math. January 23, 2022. Simons Foundation. en-US. January 23, 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20220123011430/https://www.simonsfoundation.org/2020/05/06/hilberts-problems-23-and-math/. live.
- Book: Feferman
, Solomon
. Deciding the undecidable: Wrestling with Hilbert's problems . Solomon Feferman . [{{GBurl|id=1rjnCwAAQBAJ}}
In the Light of Logic
]. 1998 . Oxford University Press . 978-0-19-508030-8 . 3–27 . Logic and Computation in Philosophy series . https://math.stanford.edu/~feferman/papers/deciding.pdf . November 29, 2022.
- Web site: The Millennium Prize Problems. Clay Mathematics Institute. January 23, 2022. July 3, 2015. https://web.archive.org/web/20150703184941/http://www.claymath.org/millennium-problems/millennium-prize-problems. live.
- Web site: Millennium Problems. Clay Mathematics Institute. January 23, 2022. December 20, 2018. https://web.archive.org/web/20181220122925/http://www.claymath.org/millennium-problems. live.