On Numbers and Games explained
On Numbers and Games is a mathematics book by John Horton Conway first published in 1976.[1] The book is written by a pre-eminent mathematician, and is directed at other mathematicians. The material is, however, developed in a playful and unpretentious manner and many chapters are accessible to non-mathematicians. Martin Gardner discussed the book at length, particularly Conway's construction of surreal numbers, in his Mathematical Games column in Scientific American in September 1976.[2]
The book is roughly divided into two sections: the first half (or Zeroth Part), on numbers, the second half (or First Part), on games. In the Zeroth Part, Conway provides axioms for arithmetic: addition, subtraction, multiplication, division and inequality. This allows an axiomatic construction of numbers and ordinal arithmetic, namely, the integers, reals, the countable infinity, and entire towers of infinite ordinals. The object to which these axioms apply takes the form, which can be interpreted as a specialized kind of set; a kind of two-sided set. By insisting that LDedekind cut. The resulting construction yields a field, now called the surreal numbers. The ordinals are embedded in this field. The construction is rooted in axiomatic set theory, and is closely related to the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms. In the original book, Conway simply refers to this field as "the numbers". The term "surreal numbers" is adopted later, at the suggestion of Donald Knuth.
In the First Part, Conway notes that, by dropping the constraint that Lclass of all two-player games. The axioms for greater than and less than are seen to be a natural ordering on games, corresponding to which of the two players may win. The remainder of the book is devoted to exploring a number of different (non-traditional, mathematically inspired) two-player games, such as nim, hackenbush, and the map-coloring games col and snort. The development includes their scoring, a review of the Sprague–Grundy theorem, and the inter-relationships to numbers, including their relationship to infinitesimals.
The book was first published by Academic Press in 1976,, and a second edition was released by A K Peters in 2001 .
Zeroth Part ... On Numbers
See main article: Surreal numbers. In the Zeroth Part, Chapter 0, Conway introduces a specialized form of set notation, having the form, where L and R are again of this form, built recursively, terminating in
, which is to be read as an analog of the empty set. Given this object, axiomatic definitions for addition, subtraction, multiplication, division and inequality may be given. As long as one insists that L
surreal numbers. The notation then resembles the Dedekind cut.The ordinal
is built by transfinite induction. As with conventional ordinals,
can be defined. Thanks to the axiomatic definition of subtraction,
can also be coherently defined: it is strictly less than
, and obeys the "obvious" equality
Yet, it is still larger than any natural number.The construction enables an entire zoo of peculiar numbers, the surreals, which form a field. Examples include
,
,
,
and similar.First Part ... and Games
In the First Part, Conway abandons the constraint that LLeft and Right. Each player has a set of games called options to choose from in turn. Games are written where L is the set of Left's options and R is the set of Right's options.[3] At the start there are no games at all, so the empty set (i.e., the set with no members) is the only set of options we can provide to the players. This defines the game
, which is called 0. We consider a player who must play a turn but has no options to have lost the game. Given this game 0 there are now two possible sets of options, the empty set and the set whose only element is zero. The game is called 1, and the game is called -1. The game is called
, and is the first game we find that is not a number.All numbers are positive, negative, or zero, and we say that a game is positive if Left has a winning strategy, negative if Right has a winning strategy, or zero if the second player has a winning strategy. Games that are not numbers have a fourth possibility: they may be fuzzy, meaning that the first player has a winning strategy. * is a fuzzy game.[4]
See also
References
- Fraenkel, Aviezri S.. Aviezri Fraenkel. Review: On numbers and games, by J. H. Conway; and Surreal numbers, by D. E. Knuth. Bull. Amer. Math. Soc.. 1978. 84. 6. 1328–1336. 10.1090/s0002-9904-1978-14564-9. free.
- Martin . Gardner . Mathematical Games . September 1976 . . 235 . 3.
- Alternatively, we often list the elements of the sets of options to save on braces. This causes no confusion as long as we can tell whether a singleton option is a game or a set of games.
- Dierk . Schleicher . Michael . Stoll . An Introduction to Conway's Games and Numbers . Moscow Math Journal . 6 . 2 . 2006 . 359–388. 10.17323/1609-4514-2006-6-2-359-388 . math.CO/0410026 .