Numbering (computability theory) explained

In computability theory a numbering is the assignment of natural numbers to a set of objects such as functions, rational numbers, graphs, or words in some formal language. A numbering can be used to transfer the idea of computability[1] and related concepts, which are originally defined on the natural numbers using computable functions, to these different types of objects.

Common examples of numberings include Gödel numberings in first-order logic, the description numbers that arise from universal Turing machines and admissible numberings of the set of partial computable functions.

Definition and examples

A numbering of a set

S

is a surjective partial function from

N

to S (Ershov 1999:477). The value of a numbering ν at a number i (if defined) is often written νi instead of the usual

\nu(i)

.

Examples of numberings include:

N

has a numbering

\gamma

, defined so that

\gamma(0)=\emptyset

and so that, for each finite nonempty set

A=\{a0,\ldots,ak\}

,

\gamma(nA)=A

where

nA=\sumi

ai
2
(Ershov 1999:477). This numbering is a (partial) bijection.

\varphii

of the computable partial functions can be used to define a numbering W of the recursively enumerable sets, by letting by W(i) be the domain of φi. This numbering will be surjective (like all numberings) but not injective: there will be distinct numbers that map to the same recursively enumerable set under W.

Types of numberings

A numbering is total if it is a total function. If the domain of a partial numbering is recursively enumerable then there always exists an equivalent total numbering (equivalence of numberings is defined below).

A numbering η is decidable if the set

\{(x,y):η(x)=η(y)\}

is a decidable set.

A numbering η is single-valued if η(x) = η(y) if and only if x=y; in other words if η is an injective function. A single-valued numbering of the set of partial computable functions is called a Friedberg numbering.

Comparison of numberings

There is a preorder on the set of all numberings. Let

\nu1:N\rightharpoonupS

and

\nu2:N\rightharpoonupS

be two numberings. Then

\nu1

is reducible to

\nu2

, written

\nu1\le\nu2

, if

\existsf\inP(1)\foralli\inDomain(\nu1):\nu1(i)=\nu2\circf(i).

If

\nu1\le\nu2

and

\nu1\ge\nu2

then

\nu1

is equivalent to

\nu2

; this is written

\nu1\equiv\nu2

.

Computable numberings

When the objects of the set S being numbered are sufficiently "constructive", it is common to look at numberings that can be effectively decoded (Ershov 1999:486). For example, if S consists of recursively enumerable sets, the numbering η is computable if the set of pairs (x,y) where yη(x) is recursively enumerable. Similarly, a numbering g of partial functions is computable if the relation R(x,y,z) = "[''g''(''x'')](y) = z" is partial recursive (Ershov 1999:487).

A computable numbering is called principal if every computable numbering of the same set is reducible to it. Both the set of all recursively enumerable subsets of

N

and the set of all partial computable functions have principle numberings (Ershov 1999:487). A principle numbering of the set of partial recursive functions is known as an admissible numbering in the literature.

See also

References

Notes and References

  1. Web site: Computability Theory - an overview ScienceDirect Topics. 2021-01-19. www.sciencedirect.com.