In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, a complete theory T is said to satisfy NIP ("not the independence property") if none of its formulae satisfy the independence property—that is, if none of its formulae can pick out any given subset of an arbitrarily large finite set.
Let T be a complete L-theory. An L-formula φ(x,y) is said to have the independence property (with respect to x, y) if in every model M of T there is, for each n = < ω, a family of tuples b0,...,bn-1 such that for each of the 2n subsets X of n there is a tuple a in M for which
M\models\varphi(\boldsymbol{a},\boldsymbol{b}i) \Leftrightarrow i\inX.
In the nomenclature of Vapnik–Chervonenkis theory, we may say that a collection S of subsets of X shatters a set B ⊆ X if every subset of B is of the form B ∩ S for some S ∈ S. Then T has the independence property if in some model M of T there is a definable family (Sa | a∈Mn) ⊆ Mk that shatters arbitrarily large finite subsets of Mk. In other words, (Sa | a∈Mn) has infinite Vapnik–Chervonenkis dimension.
Any complete theory T that has the independence property is unstable.[1]
In arithmetic, i.e. the structure (N,+,·), the formula "y divides x" has the independence property.[2] This formula is just
(\existsk)(y ⋅ k=x).
Every o-minimal theory satisfies NIP.[3] This fact has had unexpected applications to neural network learning.[4]
Examples of NIP theories include also the theories of all the following structures:[5] linear orders, trees, abelian linearly ordered groups, algebraically closed valued fields, and the p-adic field for any p.
. Wilfrid Hodges . . Model theory . registration . 1993 . 978-0-521-30442-9 .