Maximal and minimal elements explained
of some preordered set is an element of
that is not smaller than any other element in
. A
minimal element of a subset
of some preordered set is defined
dually as an element of
that is not greater than any other element in
.
The notions of maximal and minimal elements are weaker than those of greatest element and least element which are also known, respectively, as maximum and minimum. The maximum of a subset
of a preordered set is an element of
which is greater than or equal to any other element of
and the minimum of
is again defined dually. In the particular case of a
partially ordered set, while there can be at most one maximum and at most one minimum there may be multiple maximal or minimal elements.
[1] Specializing further to
totally ordered sets, the notions of maximal element and maximum coincide, and the notions of minimal element and minimum coincide.
As an example, in the collectionordered by containment, the element is minimal as it contains no sets in the collection, the element is maximal as there are no sets in the collection which contain it, the element is neither, and the element is both minimal and maximal. By contrast, neither a maximum nor a minimum exists for
Zorn's lemma states that every partially ordered set for which every totally ordered subset has an upper bound contains at least one maximal element. This lemma is equivalent to the well-ordering theorem and the axiom of choice[2] and implies major results in other mathematical areas like the Hahn–Banach theorem, the Kirszbraun theorem, Tychonoff's theorem, the existence of a Hamel basis for every vector space, and the existence of an algebraic closure for every field.
Definition
Let
be a preordered set and let
is an element
such that
if
satisfies
then necessarily
Similarly, is an element
such that
if
satisfies
then necessarily
Equivalently,
is a minimal element of
with respect to
if and only if
is a maximal element of
with respect to
where by definition,
if and only if
(for all
).
If the subset
is not specified then it should be assumed that
Explicitly, a (respectively,) is a maximal (resp. minimal) element of
with respect to
If the preordered set
also happens to be a
partially ordered set (or more generally, if the restriction
is a partially ordered set) then
is a maximal element of
if and only if
contains no element strictly greater than
explicitly, this means that there does not exist any element
such that
and
The characterization for minimal elements is obtained by using
in place of
Existence and uniqueness
Maximal elements need not exist.
where
denotes the real numbers. For all
but
(that is,
but not
).
S=\{s\in\Q~:~1\leqs2\leq2\},
where
denotes the
rational numbers and where
is irrational.
In general
is only a partial order on
If
is a maximal element and
then it remains possible that neither
nor
This leaves open the possibility that there exist more than one maximal elements.
a1<b1>a2<b2>a3<b3>\ldots,
all the
are minimal and all
are maximal, as shown in the image.
- Example 4: Let A be a set with at least two elements and let
be the subset of the
power set
consisting of
singleton subsets, partially ordered by
This is the discrete poset where no two elements are comparable and thus every element
is maximal (and minimal); moreover, for any distinct
neither
nor
Greatest and least elements
See main article: article and Greatest and least elements. For a partially ordered set
the irreflexive kernel of
is denoted as
and is defined by
if
and
For arbitrary members
exactly one of the following cases applies:
and
are incomparable.Given a subset
and some
- if case 1 never applies for any
then
is a maximal element of
as defined above;
- if case 1 and 4 never applies for any
then
is called a of
Thus the definition of a greatest element is stronger than that of a maximal element.
Equivalently, a greatest element of a subset
can be defined as an element of
that is greater than every other element of
A subset may have at most one greatest element.
[3] The greatest element of
if it exists, is also a maximal element of
[4] and the only one.
[5] By
contraposition, if
has several maximal elements, it cannot have a greatest element; see example 3.If
satisfies the
ascending chain condition, a subset
of
has a greatest element
if, and only if, it has one maximal element.
[6] When the restriction of
to
is a
total order (
in the topmost picture is an example), then the notions of maximal element and greatest element coincide.
[7] This is not a necessary condition: whenever
has a greatest element, the notions coincide, too, as stated above.If the notions of maximal element and greatest element coincide on every two-element subset
of
then
is a total order on
[8] Dual to greatest is the notion of least element that relates to minimal in the same way as greatest to maximal.
Directed sets
In a totally ordered set, the terms maximal element and greatest element coincide, which is why both terms are used interchangeably in fields like analysis where only total orders are considered. This observation applies not only to totally ordered subsets of any partially ordered set, but also to their order theoretic generalization via directed sets. In a directed set, every pair of elements (particularly pairs of incomparable elements) has a common upper bound within the set. If a directed set has a maximal element, it is also its greatest element,[9] and hence its only maximal element. For a directed set without maximal or greatest elements, see examples 1 and 2 above.
Similar conclusions are true for minimal elements.
Further introductory information is found in the article on order theory.
Properties
- Each finite nonempty subset
has both maximal and minimal elements. An infinite subset need not have any of them, for example, the
integers
with the usual order.
- The set of maximal elements of a subset
is always an
antichain, that is, no two different maximal elements of
are comparable. The same applies to minimal elements.
Examples
Consumer theory
In economics, one may relax the axiom of antisymmetry, using preorders (generally total preorders) instead of partial orders; the notion analogous to maximal element is very similar, but different terminology is used, as detailed below.
In consumer theory the consumption space is some set
, usually the positive orthant of some vector space so that each
represents a quantity of consumption specified for each existing commodity in theeconomy.
Preferences of a consumer are usually represented by a total preorder
so that
and
reads:
is at most as preferred as
. When
and
it is interpreted that the consumer is indifferent between
and
but is no reason to conclude that
preference relations are never assumed to be antisymmetric. In this context, for any
an element
is said to be a
maximal element if
implies
where it is interpreted as a consumption bundle that is not dominated by any other bundle in the sense that
that is
and not
It should be remarked that the formal definition looks very much like that of a greatest element for an ordered set. However, when
is only a preorder, an element
with the property above behaves very much like a maximal element in an ordering. For instance, a maximal element
is not unique for
does not preclude the possibility that
(while
and
do not imply
but simply indifference
). The notion of greatest element for a preference preorder would be that of
most preferred choice. That is, some
with
implies
An obvious application is to the definition of demand correspondence. Let
be the class of functionals on
. An element
is called a
price functional or
price system and maps every consumption bundle
into its market value
. The
budget correspondence is a correspondence
mapping any price system and any level of income into a subset
The demand correspondence maps any price
and any level of income
into the set of
-maximal elements of
.
It is called demand correspondence because the theory predicts that for
and
given, the
rational choice of a consumer
will be some element
Related notions
A subset
of a partially ordered set
is said to be
cofinal if for every
there exists some
such that
Every cofinal subset of a partially ordered set with maximal elements must contain all maximal elements.
A subset
of a partially ordered set
is said to be a
lower set of
if it is downward closed: if
and
then
Every lower set
of a finite ordered set
is equal to the smallest lower set containing all maximal elements of
Notes
- Proofs
Notes and References
- .
- Book: Jech
, Thomas
. Thomas Jech. The Axiom of Choice. 2008. originally published in 1973. Dover Publications. 978-0-486-46624-8.
- If
and
are both greatest, then
and
and hence
by antisymmetry.
- If
is the greatest element of
and
then
By antisymmetry, this renders (
and
) impossible.
- If
is a maximal element then
(because
is greatest) and thus
since
is maximal.
see above. - : Assume for contradiction that
has just one maximal element,
but no greatest element. Since
is not greatest, some
must exist that is incomparable to
Hence
cannot be maximal, that is,
must hold for some
The latter must be incomparable to
too, since
contradicts
's maximality while
contradicts the incomparability of
and
Repeating this argument, an infinite ascending chain
can be found (such that each
is incomparable to
and not maximal). This contradicts the ascending chain condition.
- Let
be a maximal element, for any
either
or
In the second case, the definition of maximal element requires that
so it follows that
In other words,
is a greatest element.
- If
were incomparable, then
would have two maximal, but no greatest element, contradicting the coincidence.
- Let
be maximal. Let
be arbitrary. Then the common upper bound
of
and
satisfies
, so
by maximality. Since
holds by definition of
, we have
. Hence
is the greatest element.